Jump to content

Active intellect

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Inmedieval philosophy,theactive intellect(Latin:intellectus agens;also translated asagent intellect,active intelligence,active reason,orproductive intellect) is theformal(morphe) aspect of the intellect (nous), according to theAristoteliantheory ofhylomorphism.The nature of the active intellect was a major theme of late classical and medieval philosophy. Various thinkers sought to reconcile their commitment to Aristotle's account of the body and soul to their own theological commitments. At stake in particular was in what way Aristotle's account of an incorporealsoulmight contribute to understanding ofdeityandcreation.

Aristotle's conception

[edit]

The idea is first encountered in two ofAristotle'sworks.

A passage inDe Anima,Book IIIexplains "how the human intellect passes from its original state, in which it does not think, to a subsequent state, in which it does." He inferred that theenergeia/dynamisdistinction must also exist in the soul itself.[1]Aristotle distinguished two separable types of intellect or nous which he believed were both necessary in order to explain human thinking. What modern scholars call the "passive intellect"is material and destructible and it receives theintelligible formsof things. It is acted upon. In contrast, the active intellect is what acts upon the passive intellect. It is required to make potential knowledge into actual knowledge, in the same way that light makes potential colors into actual colors. Aristotle describes this active intellect as something separate, everlasting, unchanging, and immaterial. It is the passive or material intellect where human thinking and remembering happens, because these involve change.

Another passage which is traditionally read together with the De Anima passage is inMetaphysics,Book XII, Ch. 7–10.[2]Aristotle again distinguishes between the active andpassiveintellects, but this time he equates the active intellect with the "unmoved mover"andGod.He explains that when people have real knowledge, their thinking is, for a time receiving, or partaking of, this energeia of the nous (active intellect).[3]

Interpretations

[edit]

Sachs comments that the nature of the active intellect was "the source of a massive amount of commentary and of fierce disagreement"; elsewhere, chapter 5 ofDe Animahas been referred to as "the most intensely studied sentences in the history of philosophy".[2]As Davidson remarks:

Just what Aristotle meant by potential intellect and active intellect – terms not even explicit in theDe animaand at best implied – and just how he understood the interaction between them remains moot. Students of the history of philosophy continue to debate Aristotle's intent, particularly the question whether he considered the active intellect to be an aspect of the human soul or an entity existing independently of man.[1]

Alexander of Aphrodisiasregarded the active intellect as a power external to the human mind, going so far as to identify it with God.[4]The reason for positing a single external Agent Intellect is that all (rational) human beings are considered by Aristotelians to possess or have access to a fixed and stable set of concepts, a unified correct knowledge of the universe. The only way that all human minds could possess the same correct knowledge is if they all had access to some central knowledge store, as terminals might have access to a mainframe computer (Kraemer 2003). This mainframe is the Agent Intellect, the "mind" of the universe, which makes all other cognition possible.

Al-FarabiandAvicennaandMaimonides,agreed with the "external" interpretation of active intellect, and held that the active intellect was the lowest of the ten emanations descending through thecelestial spheres.Maimonides cited it in his definition ofprophecywhere:

Prophecy is, in truth and reality, an emanation sent forth by theDivine Beingthrough the medium of the Active Intellect, in the first instance to man'srational faculty,and then to hisimaginative faculty.[5]

The more strict Aristotelians,AvempaceandAverroes,wrote about how one could conjoin oneself with the active intellect, thus attaining a kind of philosophical enlightenment. In Medieval and Renaissance Europe some thinkers, such asSiger of Brabant,adopted the interpretation of Averroes on every point, as did the later school of "Paduan Averroists".

Thomas Aquinaselaborated on Aristotle's distinction between the active intellect and passive intellect in hisDisputed Questions on the Souland his commentary on Aristotle'sDe Anima,arguing, against Averroes, that the active intellect is part of the individual human personality. In hisSumma Theologica,Aquinas states that "according to the teaching of our Faith, this separated intellect is God Himself, who is the creator of the soul and in whom alone the soul is beatified."[6]CitingGregory of Nyssa,he said "man has intellective understanding along with the angels" which are called 'minds' and 'intellects' because they have no other power than the intellective power and the will (Question 79, Article 1). A third school, of "Alexandrists", rejected the argument linking the active intellect to theimmortalityof the soul, while hastening to add that they still believed in immortality as a matter of religious faith. (SeePietro Pomponazzi;Cesare Cremonini.)

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^abDavidson, Herbert (1992),Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes, on Intellect,Oxford University Press,p. 3.
  2. ^abSachs, Joe (2001),Aristotle's On the Soul and On Memory and Recollection,Green Lion Press.
  3. ^SeeMetaphysics1072b.
  4. ^Davidson, Herbert (1992),Alfarabi, Avicenna, and Averroes, on Intellect,Oxford University Press
  5. ^Maimonides,Guide for the Perplexed(translator:Michael Friedländer), Dover: New York, 1904,p. 225.
  6. ^Summa Theologiae, part I, question 79, article 4 – Is the active intellect something that belongs to our soul?(PDF).Translated by Alfred J. Freddoso. p. 600.{{cite book}}:|website=ignored (help)

Sources

[edit]
  • Kraemer, Joel L. (2003), "The Islamic context of medieval Jewish philosophy", in Frank, Daniel H.; Leaman, Oliver (eds.),The Cambridge Companion to Medieval Jewish Philosophy,Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 38–68,ISBN978-0-521-65207-0
  • Commentarium magnum in Aristotelis De anima libros,ed. Crawford, Cambridge (Mass.) 1953: Latin translation of Averroes' long commentary on the De Anima
  • Walter Burley, Commentarium in Aristotelis De Anima L.IIICritical EditionandPalaeographytranscription by Mario Tonelotto
  • Averroes (tr. Alain de Libera),L'intelligence et la pensée,Paris 1998: French translation of Averroes' long commentary on book 3 of the De Anima
  • Essays on Aristotle'sDe Anima,ed.Nussbaumand Rorty: Oxford 1992
  • Juan Fernando Sellés (2012),El intelecto agente y los filósofos. Venturas y desventuras del supremo hallazgo aristotélico sobre el hombre,Tomo I (Siglos IV a.C. – XV), EUNSA, Pamplona, p. 650.
[edit]