Jump to content

Anarchist law

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Anarchist lawis a term variously used to describe the apparent norms regarding behavior and decision-making operative within an anarchist community from the perspective of a law-normative viewpoint. (Anarchy is not chaos, Anarchy is individualism.) Although many anarchists would consider "anarchist law" simply synonymous withnatural law,others contend law as implied in anarchy by outside observers would have additional, unique elements.[1]Over the course of the last two hundred years as anarchism has grown and evolved to include diverse strains, there have been different conceptions of "anarchist law" produced and discussed, or used in practice by anarchist networks such asPeoples' Global Action[2]orIndymedia.[3]

Non-coercion

[edit]

The most fundamental maxim of many anarchist tendencies is that no individual has the right to coerce another individual, and that everyone has the right to defend themselves against coercion (thenon-aggression principleor zero aggression principle). Systems typically considered coercive include thestate,capitalism,andinstitutional oppression.This basic principle, likemutual aid,is foundational to much of anarchist law, and indeed much of anarchist theory.Peter Kropotkin,a prominentanarcho-communist,stated it was "best summed up by the maxim 'do unto others as you would have them do unto you.'" In short, anarchist philosophy includes the "ethic of reciprocity,"but typically condones violence intended to retaliate against or dismantle systems of oppression (with the exception ofanarcho-pacifism,someChristian anarchismand other nonviolent/pacifistic movements.)[4]

Consensus-based social contracts

[edit]

Since the principle of non-coercion makes hierarchical state structures unfeasible, anarchist communities must find an alternative basis for setting the rules of engagement within a collective. Accordingly, virtually all anarchist legal models begin with the assumption that whatever rules are set in place must be freely agreed to by the entirety of the community that is to be governed by them in a setting free from coercion or intimidation. Such freely given consent constitutes asocial contract,though the exact nature of such contracts is a matter of heated debate.[5]

Some anarchist legal theorists hold that an ideal anarchist society should be based strictly onnatural lawandmutual aid,which require no social contract.[6]

However, many anarchist theorists completely reject the concept of natural law as coercive and man-made. Natural law in this view is merely disguising authoritarianism so the oppressor does not have to take credit for it.Social anarchists,mutualistsand manyindividualist anarchistsreject private property, a core principle of most natural law theories.[7]

Free association

[edit]

Free association (also calledvoluntary association) also implies the right of individuals to form those exact social contracts. This freedom to not associate means if the terms of a social contract become unacceptable to an individual member or sub-group(s) within a society, the discontented have the right to secede from the contract. They may also form new associations with others that more closely fit their needs.[8]

Mutual aid

[edit]

The principle ofmutual aid,originally identified byPeter Kropotkinas arising from natural law, is that since evolution occurs in groups – not individuals – it is evolutionarily advantageous for members of a community to assist each other. The anarchist approach to building power – and structuring power relationships – is derived from this evolutionary and biological imperative. In a nutshell the argument is that since individuals require the assistance of groups to self-actualize, individuals have a strong self-interest in the good of the community to which they belong. It follows that (freely associating) collectives of individuals working for mutual improvement and mutual goals must form the basis of any anarchist society, thus providing the sociological and economic imperative for the creation of social contracts capable of binding these self-selecting groups together.[6]

In a pre-revolutionary situation, the principle of "mutual aid" is the moral imperative that drives efforts by contemporary anarchists to provide material aid to victims of natural disasters;[9]those that are homeless or poor, and others who have been left without access to food or clean drinking water, or other basic necessities.

Enforceability

[edit]

Enforceability is one of the most controversial areas of anarchist law. Early writers such asProudhonargued that it was legitimate for working-class people to self-organize against criminals who prey on the weak, a process which would unequivocally entail some degree of coercion.[10]

Decision-making

[edit]

Common techniques fordecision-making,including decisions about the de facto laws themselves, among non-hierarchical societies include various forms of formalconsensus,[3]supermajorityvoting, "consensus minus one" anddirect democracy.[11]AnthropologistDavid Graeberargues that any community that lacks a centralized mechanism of force (a state) will naturally gravitate toward some form of consensus decision-making.

Examples

[edit]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^"Anarchism and Law".The Anarchist Library.Retrieved6 February2023.
  2. ^"Organisational Principles".Peoples' Global Action.Archivedfrom the original on 15 October 2006.Retrieved2006-10-29.
  3. ^ab"Principles of Unity".Indymedia.Archived fromthe originalon 2016-03-03.Retrieved2006-10-28.
  4. ^Tamblyn, Nathan (2019)."The Common Ground of Law and Anarchism".Liverpool Law Review.40:65–78.doi:10.1007/s10991-019-09223-1.hdl:10871/36939.S2CID155131683.Archivedfrom the original on 2020-10-09.Retrieved2020-09-24.
  5. ^Tamblyn, Nathan (April 30, 2019)."The Common Ground of Law and Anarchism".Liverpool Law Review.40(1): 65–78.doi:10.1007/s10991-019-09223-1.hdl:10871/36939.ISSN1572-8625.
  6. ^ab"Anarchist Writers – Anarchist analysis & the Anarchist FAQ".Archived fromthe original(PDF)on 2021-04-10.Retrieved2020-09-30.
  7. ^"The Myth of" Natural Law "".Archivedfrom the original on 2020-10-28.Retrieved2020-09-27.
  8. ^"Archived copy".Archivedfrom the original on 2021-08-13.Retrieved2020-09-30.{{cite web}}:CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link)
  9. ^"Katrina Relief".Archivedfrom the original on 2006-06-13.Retrieved2006-06-13.
  10. ^Ritter, Alan (1975)."Godwin, Proudhon and the Anarchist Justification of Punishment".Political Theory.3:69–87.doi:10.1177/009059177500300107.S2CID149216607.
  11. ^"A.2.11 Why are most anarchists in favour of direct democracy?".Infoshop.Archivedfrom the original on 25 October 2006.Retrieved2006-10-28.

Further reading

[edit]
  • Holterman, Thom; Henc van Maarseveen (1984).Law and Anarchism.Montréal: Black Rose Books.ISBN0-919619-10-X.
[edit]