Jump to content

Fallacy of division

Listen to this article
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Thefallacy of division[1]is aninformal fallacythat occurs when one reasons that something that is true for a whole must also be true of all or some of its parts.

An example:

  1. The second grade in Jefferson Elementary eats a lot of ice cream
  2. Carlos is a second-grader in Jefferson Elementary
  3. Therefore, Carlos eats a lot of ice cream

The converse of thisfallacyis calledfallacy of composition,which arises when one fallaciously attributes a property of some part of a thing to the thing as a whole.

If a system as a whole has some property that none of its constituents has (or perhaps, it has it but not as aresultof some constituent's having that property), this is sometimes called anemergentproperty of the system.

The termmereological fallacyrefers to approximately the same incorrect inference that properties of a whole are also properties of its parts.[2][3][4]

History[edit]

Both the fallacy of division and thefallacy of compositionwere addressed byAristotleinSophistical Refutations.

In the philosophy of the ancient GreekAnaxagoras,as claimed by the RomanatomistLucretius,[5]it was assumed that the atoms constituting a substance must themselves have the salient observed properties of that substance: so atoms of water would be wet, atoms of iron would be hard, atoms of wool would be soft, etc. This doctrine is calledhomoeomeria,and it depends on the fallacy of division.

Examples in statistics[edit]

Instatisticsanecological fallacyis a logical fallacy in the interpretation of statistical data where inferences about the nature of individuals are deduced from inference for the group to which those individuals belong. The four common statistical ecological fallacies are: confusion between ecological correlations and individual correlations, confusion between group average and total average,Simpson's paradox,and other statistical methods.[6]

See also[edit]

References[edit]

  1. ^"Division".Retrieved2024-05-10.
  2. ^M. R. Bennett; P. M. S. Hacker. 2003.Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience.Table of contents.
  3. ^Rom Harré.Behind the Mereological Fallacy.Philosophy87:3, July 2012, pp. 329-352.https://doi.org/10.1017/S0031819112000241
  4. ^P.M.S. Hacker. 2013.Before the Mereological Fallacy: A Rejoinder to Rom Harré.Philosophy,88(1), 141-148. doi:10.1017/S003181911200054X
  5. ^Brauneis, Robert (2009).Intellectual Property Protection of Fact-based Works: Copyright and Its Alternatives.Edward Elgar Publishing. p. 110.
  6. ^Burnham Terrell, Dailey (1967).Logic: A Modern Introduction to Deductive Reasoning.Holt, Rinehart and Winston. pp.160–163.

Further reading[edit]

  • Werner Ebeling; Hans-Michael Voigt.Parallel Problem Solving from Nature - PPSN IV: International Conference on Evolutionary Computation. The 4th International Conference on Parallel Problem Solving from Nature Berlin, Germany, September 22–26, 1996. Proceedings, Volume 114.Springer Science & Business Media. pp. 170–173.
  • Richard M. Grinnell; Jr., Yvonne A. Unrau.Social Work Research and Evaluation: Foundations of Evidence-Based Practice.Oxford University Press. pp. 393–394.

External links[edit]

Listen to this article(2minutes)
Spoken Wikipedia icon
This audio filewas created from a revision of this article dated 5 September 2020(2020-09-05),and does not reflect subsequent edits.