Jump to content

German idealism

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected fromGerman idealist)
The four principal German idealists, clockwise fromImmanuel Kantin the upper left:J. G. Fichte,G. W. F. Hegel,F. W. J. Schelling

German idealismis aphilosophical movementthat emerged inGermanyin the late 18th and early 19th centuries. It developed out of the work ofImmanuel Kantin the 1780s and 1790s,[1]and was closely linked both withRomanticismand the revolutionary politics of theEnlightenment.The period of German idealism after Kant is also known aspost-Kantian idealismor simplypost-Kantianism.[2]One scheme divides German idealists intotranscendental idealists,associated with Kant and Fichte, andabsolute idealists,associated with Schelling and Hegel.[3]

Meaning of idealism

[edit]

The philosophical meaning of idealism is that those properties we discover in objects are dependent on the way that those objects appear to us. These properties belong to the appearance of objects, and are not necessarily something they possess "in themselves".

History

[edit]

Immanuel Kant's work purports to bridge the two dominant philosophical schools in the 18th century:rationalism,which holds that knowledge could be attained by reason alonea priori(prior to experience), andempiricism,which holds that knowledge could be arrived at only through the sensesa posteriori(after experience), as expressed by philosopherDavid Hume,whose skepticism Kant sought to rebut.[4]

Kant's solution was to propose that, while we depend on objects of experience to know anything about the world, we can investigatea priorithe form that our thoughts can take, determining the boundaries of possible experience. Kant calls this approach "critical philosophy".It is less concerned with setting out positive doctrine than with critiquing the limits to the theories wecanset out.

There is, however, a positive doctrine: "transcendental idealism",which is distinct fromclassical idealismandsubjective idealism.On this view, the world of appearances is "empirically real and transcendentally ideal." That is, the mind plays a central role in shaping our experience of the world: we perceive phenomena intimeandspaceaccording to thecategories of the understanding.

Theorists

[edit]

The best-known German idealist thinkers, after Kant, areJ. G. Fichte,F. W. J. Schelling,andG. W. F. Hegel.Critics of Kant's project such asF. H. Jacobi,Gottlob Ernst Schulze,andSalomon Maimoninfluenced the direction the movement would take in the philosophies of his would-be successors.

Kant

[edit]

According toImmanuel Kant,the human mind is not capable of directly experiencing the external world as it is in itself. Instead, our experience of the world is mediated by the a priori categories and concepts that are inherent in the human mind. These categories and concepts, which Kant calls "transcendental" because they are necessary for any experience, structure and organize our experience of the world, but they do not provide us with direct access to the thing-in-itself, which is the ultimate reality.

Kant's transcendental idealism has two main components. The first is the idea that the human mind is not a passive recipient of sensory information, but is actively involved in shaping our experience of the world. The second is the idea that the nature of reality is ultimately unknowable to us, because our experience of the world is mediated by the structures of our own minds.

Kant restricted the domain of knowledge to objects of possible experience. His three most notable successors, however, would react against such stringent limits.[5]

Jacobi

[edit]

In 1787,Friedrich Heinrich Jacobiaddressed, in his bookOn Faith, or Idealism and Realism,Kant's concept of "thing-in-itself". Jacobi agreed that the objective thing-in-itself cannot be directly known. However, he stated, it must be taken on belief. A subject must believe that there is a real object in the external world that is related to its subjective representation. This belief is a result of revelation or immediately known, but logically unproved, truth. The real existence of a thing-in-itself is revealed or disclosed to the observing subject. In this way, the subject directly knows the ideal, subjective representations that appear in the mind, and strongly believes in the real, objective thing-in-itself that exists outside the mind. By presenting the external world as an object of belief, Jacobi aimed to legitimize belief – or faith – in general.

Reinhold

[edit]

Karl Leonhard Reinholdpublished two volumes ofLetters Concerning the Kantian Philosophyin 1790 and 1792. He tried to prove Kant's assertion that humans and other animals can know only phenomena, never things-in-themselves. In order to establish his proof, Reinhold stated anaxiomthat could not possibly be doubted. From this axiom, all knowledge ofconsciousnesscould be deduced. His axiom was: "Representation is distinguished in consciousness by the subject from the subject and object, and is referred to both."

He thereby started, not from definitions, but, from a principle that referred to representations in a conscious mind. In this way, he analyzed knowledge into (1) the knowing subject, or observer, (2) the known object, and (3) the image or representation in the subject's mind.

Schulze

[edit]

Gottlob Ernst Schulzeobjected to Kant's critical philosophy as self-contradictory. According to Kant himself, the law of cause and effect only applies to the phenomena, not between phenomena and things-in-themselves. Yet, Kant directly claims that the thing-in-itself is the cause of phenomena.

Fichte

[edit]

After Schulze had seriously criticized the notion of a thing-in-itself,Johann Gottlieb Fichteproduced a philosophy similar to Kant's, but without a thing-in-itself. Fichte asserted that our representations are the productions of the "transcendental ego", that is, the knowing subject. For him, there is no external thing-in-itself. On the contrary, the subject is the source of the external thing, object, or non-ego.

Fichte claimed that this truth was apparent by means of intellectual intuition. That is, the truth can be immediately seen by the use of reason.

Schelling

[edit]

Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling(1775–1854) claimed that the Fichte's "I" needs the Not-I, because there is no subject without object, and vice versa. So subjective representations are identical to the extended objects which are external to the mind. According to Schelling's "absolute identity" or "indifferentism", there is no difference between the subjective and the objective, that is, the ideal and the real.

Schleiermacher

[edit]

Friedrich Schleiermacherwas a theologian who asserted that the ideal and the real are united in God. He understood the ideal as the subjective mental activities of thought, intellect, and reason. The real was, for him, the objective area of nature and physical being. Schleiermacher declared that the unity of the ideal and the real is manifested in God. The two divisions do not have a productive or causal effect on each other. Rather, they are both equally existent in the absolute transcendental entity which is God.

Maimon

[edit]

Salomon Maimoninfluenced German idealism by criticizing Kant's dichotomies, claiming that Kant did not explain how opposites such as sensibility and understanding could relate to each other. As he clearly saw, this presented a serious skeptical objection to the Kantian project:

By thus pointing out these problematic dualisms, Maimon and the neo-Humeancritics left a foothold open for skepticism within the framework of Kant’s own philosophy. For now the question arose how two such heterogeneous realms as the intellectual and the sensible could be known to correspond with one another. The problem was no longer how we know that our representations correspond with things in themselves but how we know thata prioriconcepts apply toa posterioriintuitions.[6]

Maimon attempted to resolve this problem by introducing the concept of "infinite mind". For this reason, Maimon can be said to have returned to pre-Kantian transcendent speculation. In the words ofFrederick C. Beiser,"by reviving metaphysical ideas from within the problematic of the critical philosophy, he gave them a new legitimacy and opened up the possibility for a critical resurrection of metaphysics.[7]

Hegel

[edit]

Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegelresponded to Kant's philosophy by suggesting that the unsolvable contradictions given by Kant in hisAntinomies of Pure Reasonapplied more broadly to reality as such. Given that abstract thought is thus limited, he went on to consider how historical formations give rise to different philosophies and ways of thinking. InThe Phenomenology of Spirit,he went on to trace formations ofself-consciousnessthrough history and the importance of other people in the awakening of self-consciousness. Thus Hegel introduced two important ideas to metaphysics and philosophy: the integral importance of history and intersubjectivity.

Hegel also claims tosublatethe traditional concept ofGodwith his concept ofabsolute spirit.Baruch Spinoza,who changed the anthropomorphic concept of God into that of an underlying substance, was praised by Hegel whose concept of absolute knowing fulfilled a similar function. Hegel claimed that "You are either a Spinozist or not a philosopher at all".[8]

Responses

[edit]

Neo-Kantianism

[edit]

Neo-Kantianism emphasizes the critical dimension of Kant's philosophy as against the perceived excesses of German Idealism. It was the dominant philosophy in Germany during the late 19th and early 20th centuries. Although there was considerable disagreement among the neo-Kantians themselves, they shared a commitment to some version of the "transcendental method".[9]

British idealism

[edit]

In England, during the nineteenth century, philosopherThomas Hill Greenembraced German Idealism in order to support Christianmonotheismas a basis for morality. His philosophy attempted to account for an eternal consciousness ormindthat was similar toBerkeley's concept ofGod.John Rodman, in the introduction to his book on Thomas Hill Green's political theory, wrote: "Green is best seen as an exponent of German idealism as an answer to the dilemma posed by the discrediting of Christianity...."[10]

United States

[edit]

"German idealism was initially introduced to the broader community of Americanliteratithrough aVermontintellectual,James Marsh.Studying theology withMoses StuartatAndover Seminaryin the early 1820s, Marsh sought aChristian theologythat would 'keep alive the heart in the head.' "[11]Some American theologians and churchmen found value in German Idealism's theological concept of the infinite Absolute Ideal orGeist[Spirit]. It provided a religious alternative to the traditional Christian concept of theDeity.[12]The Absolute IdealWeltgeist[World Spirit] was invoked by American ministers as they "turned to German idealism in the hope of finding comfort against English positivism and empiricism."[13]German idealism was a substitute for religion after the Civil War when "Americans were drawn to German idealism because of a 'loss of faith in traditional cosmic explanations.'"[14]"By the early 1870s, the infiltration of German idealism was so pronounced thatWalt Whitmandeclared in his personal notes that 'Only Hegel is fit for America — is large enough and free enough.' "[15]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^Beiser, Frederick C.(2002).German Idealism: The Struggle Against Subjectivism, 1781–1801.Vol. Part I.Harvard University Press.
  2. ^Pinkard, Terry(2002).German Philosophy 1760–1860: The Legacy of Idealism.Cambridge University Press.p. 217.
  3. ^Dunham, Jeremy;Grant, Iain Hamilton;Watson, Sean (2011).Idealism: A History of a Philosophy.Durham:McGill-Queen's University Press.p. 303 n. 4.
  4. ^Dudley, Will.Understanding German Idealism.pp. 3–6.ISBN9781844653935.
  5. ^"Fichte: Kantian or Spinozian? Three Interpretations of the Absolute I" by Alexandre Guilherme,South African Journal of Philosophy,(2010), Volume 29, Number 1, p. 14.
  6. ^Beiser, Frederick C.(2000). "Chapter I: The Enlightenment and idealism Section V: The meta-critical campaign". InAmeriks, Karl(ed.).The Cambridge Companion to German Idealism.Cambridge University Press.p. 28.
  7. ^Beiser, Frederick C.(1987). "10: Maimon's Critical Philosophy".The Fate of Reason: German Philosophy from Kant to Fichte.Harvard University Press.p. 287.
  8. ^Hegel's Lectures on the History of Philosophy,Section 2, Chapter 1, A2. Spinoza. General Criticism of Spinoza's Philosophy, Second Point of View (cf. paragraph beginning with "The second point to be considered..." )
  9. ^Heis, Jeremy, "Neo-Kantianism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/neo-kantianism/>.
  10. ^John Rodman,The Political Theory of T. H. Green,New York: Appleton Century–Crofts, 1964, "Introduction"
  11. ^James Marsh, as quoted by James A. Good (2002) in volume 2 of hisThe early American reception of German idealism,p. 43.
  12. ^“The Absolute or World Spirit was easily identified with the God of Christianity....”, (Morton White(Ed.)The Mentor Philosophers:The Age of Analysis: twentieth century philosophers,Houghton Mifflin, 1955, Chapter 1, “The Decline and Fall of the Absolute” )
  13. ^Schneider, Herbert (1963).History of American philosophy(2nd ed.). New York:Columbia University Press.p. 376.
  14. ^Dowler, Lawrence (1974).The New Idealism(Ph.D.).University of Maryland.p. 13.as quoted inGood, James Allan.A search for unity in diversity.p. 83.
  15. ^Walt Whitman,The complete writings,vol. 9, p. 170, as quoted in James A. Good (2005),A search for unity in diversity,ch. 2, p. 57.

Bibliography

[edit]
[edit]