Jump to content

Arthur Danto

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Arthur Coleman Danto
Danto, 2012
Born(1924-01-01)January 1, 1924
DiedOctober 25, 2013(2013-10-25)(aged 89)
New York City, U.S.
Alma materWayne State University
Columbia University
Era20th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolAnalytic
Main interests
Philosophy of art
Philosophy of history
Philosophy of action
Notable ideas
Narrative sentences
Basic actions
End of Art
Post-historical Art
Indiscernibles

Arthur Coleman Danto(January 1, 1924 – October 25, 2013) was an American art critic, philosopher, and professor atColumbia University.He was best known for having been a long-time art critic forThe Nationand for his work in philosophicalaestheticsandphilosophy of history,though he contributed significantly to a number of fields, including thephilosophy of action.His interests included thought, feeling,philosophy of art,theories ofrepresentation,philosophical psychology,Hegel's aesthetics, and the philosophersFriedrich NietzscheandJean-Paul Sartre.

Life and career[edit]

Danto was born inAnn Arbor, Michigan,January 1, 1924, and grew up inDetroit.[1]He was raised in aReform Jewishhome.[2]After spending two years in the Army, Danto studied art and history at Wayne University (nowWayne State University). While an undergraduate he intended to become an artist, and began making prints in the Expressionist style in 1947 (these are now great rarities). He then pursued graduate study in philosophy atColumbia University.[1]From 1949 to 1950, Danto studied in Paris on aFulbright scholarshipunderJean Wahl,[3]and in 1951 returned to teach at Columbia.[1]

Upon retirement in 1992 he was named Johnsonian Professor Emeritus of Philosophy.[1]He was twice awarded fellowships from theGuggenheim Foundationand was a member of theAmerican Academy of Arts and Sciences,elected in 1980. He was one of the signers of theHumanist Manifesto.[4]Danto died on October 25, 2013, aged 89 in Manhattan, New York City.[1]

Philosophical work[edit]

Arthur Danto argued that "a problem is not a philosophical problem unless it is possible to imagine that its solution will consist in showing how appearance has been taken for reality."[5]While science deals with empirical problems, philosophy according to Danto examines indiscernible differences that lie outside of experience.[6]Noel Carroll, writing as an art critic, has criticized Danto's anthropology stating that Danto "believe[d] that persons are essentially systems of representation."[7]

"Artworld" and the definition of art[edit]

Danto laid the groundwork for an institutional definition of art[8]that sought to answer the questions raised by the emerging phenomenon of twentieth-century art. The definition of the term "art" is a subject of constant contention and many books and journal articles have been published arguing over the answer to the question "What is Art?"In terms ofclassificatory disputes about art,Danto takes a conventional approach. Non-conventional definitions take a concept like the aesthetic as an intrinsic characteristic in order to account for the phenomena of art. Conventional definitions reject this connection to aesthetic, formal, or expressive properties as essential to defining art but rather, in either an institutional or historical sense, say that "art" is basically a sociological category. Danto's "institutional definition of art" defines art as whatever art schools, museums, and artists consider art, regardless of further formal definition. Danto wrote on this subject in several of his works and a detailed treatment is to be found inTransfiguration of the Commonplace.[9][10]

Danto stated, "A work of art is a meaning given embodiment." Danto further stated, also inVeeryjournal, "Criticism, other than of content, is really of the mode of embodiment."[11]

The 1964 essay "The Artworld" in which Danto coined the term "artworld" (as opposed to the existing "art world",though they mean the same), by which he meant cultural context or" an atmosphere ofart theory",[12]first appeared inThe Journal of Philosophyand has since been widely reprinted. It has had considerable influence on aesthetic philosophy and, according to professor of philosophyStephen David Ross,"especially uponGeorge Dickie'sinstitutional theory of art.Dickie defined an art work as an artifact 'which has had conferred upon it the status of candidate for appreciation by some person or persons acting in behalf of a certain social institution (the artworld)' (p. 43.) "[13]

According to theStanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,"Danto's definition has been glossed as follows: something is a work of art if and only if (i) it has a subject (ii) about which it projects some attitude or point of view (has a style) (iii) by means of rhetorical ellipsis (usually metaphorical) which ellipsis engages audience participation in filling in what is missing, and (iv) where the work in question and the interpretations thereof require an art historical context (Danto withNoël Carroll). Clause (iv) is what makes the definition institutionalist. The view has been criticized for entailing that art criticism written in a highly rhetorical style is art, lacking but requiring an independent account of what makes a context art historical, and for not applying to music. "[12]

After about 2005, Danto attempted to streamline his definition of art down to two principles: (i) art must have content or meaning and (ii) the art must embody that meaning in some appropriate manner.[14]

The philosophical disenfranchisement of art[edit]

Danto's Hegelian position on the history of art and its reception was emphasized in his 1984 plenary address to the World Congress of Aesthetics held in Montreal in that year, and later published as the opening chapter in his bookThe Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art.[15]In the essay, Danto takes a contrary position to that of Plato who emphasized that art and artistic endeavors occupied an inferior position of importance among the endeavors of philosophers. Danto summarizes this ancient position of the Socratics with the phrase that "art is dangerous" on page four of the essay, which he then criticizes in the remainder of the essay.[16]

The Hegelian end of art[edit]

The basic meaning of the term "art" has changed several times over the centuries and continued to evolve during the 20th century as well. Danto describes the history of Art in his own contemporary version ofHegel'sdialectical history of art. "Danto is not claiming that no-one is making art anymore; nor is he claiming that no good art is being made any more. But he thinks that a certain history of western art has come to an end, in about the way that Hegel suggested it would."[17]The "end of art" refers to the beginning of our modern era of art in which art no longer adheres to the constraints ofimitation theorybut serves a new purpose. Art began with an "era of imitation, followed by an era of ideology, followed by our post-historical era in which, with qualification, anything goes... In our narrative, at first only mimesis [imitation] was art, then several things were art but each tried to extinguish its competitors, and then, finally, it became apparent that there were no stylistic or philosophical constraints. There is no special way works of art have to be. And that is the present and, I should say, the final moment in the master narrative. It is the end of the story."[18]

Art criticism[edit]

Arthur Danto was an art critic forThe Nationfrom 1984 to 2009, and also published numerous articles in other journals. In addition, he was an editor ofThe Journal of Philosophyand a contributing editor of theNaked Punch ReviewandArtforum.Inart criticism,he published several collected essays, includingEncounters and Reflections: Art in the Historical Present(Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 1990), which won theNational Book Critics CirclePrize for Criticism in 1990;Beyond the Brillo Box: The Visual Arts in Post-Historical Perspective(Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 1992);Playing With the Edge: The Photographic Achievement ofRobert Mapplethorpe(University of California, 1995);The Madonna of the Future: Essays in a Pluralistic Art World(Farrar, Straus & Giroux, 2000); andUnnatural Wonders: Essays from the Gap Between Art and Life(Columbia University Press, 2007).

In 1996, he received theFrank Jewett MatherAward for art criticism from theCollege Art Association.[19]Danto artist friendSean Scully,to honor his long-term friendship with Danto, published the bookDanto on Scully,bringing together the series of five essays Danto had written on the artist over the previous 20 years after Danto's death in 2013.[20]

Publications[edit]

Books[edit]

Essay collections[edit]

Articles, book chapters and other works[edit]

Notes[edit]

  1. ^abcdeJohnson, Ken(October 27, 2013)."Arthur C. Danto, a Philosopher of Art, Is Dead at 89".The New York Times.RetrievedOctober 28,2013.
  2. ^Italie, Hillel (October 28, 2013)."Groundbreaking art critic Arthur Danto dies at 89".The Times of Israel.RetrievedAugust 6,2017.
  3. ^Arthur Danto - Interviewed by Zoe SutherlandArchived2018-09-29 at theWayback Machine.Naked Punch,10 July 2010
  4. ^"Humanist Manifesto II".American Humanist Association. Archived fromthe originalon October 20, 2012.RetrievedOctober 7,2012.
  5. ^Arthur Danto,Connections to the World: The Basic Concepts of Philosophy(New York: Harper and Row, 1989), p.6.
  6. ^Noel Carroll, "Danto's Comic Vision: Philosophical Method and Literary Style,"Philosophy and Literature39.2 (October 2015), p. 556.
  7. ^Noel Carroll, "Danto's Comic Vision: Philosophical Method and Literary Style,"Philosophy and Literature39.2 (October 2015), p. 563 n. 8.
  8. ^This theory has been described as an "influential theory about the nature of art", according toPhilosophy Now, November 2013
  9. ^Danto, Arthur(1981).The transfiguration of the commonplace: a philosophy of art.Harvard University Press.ISBN978-0-674-90346-3.
  10. ^Maes, Hans R.V. and Puolakka, Kalle (2012)"Arthur Danto: The Transfiguration of the Commonplace,"[Preprint,final version in:]50 Key Texts in Art History.Routledge. ISBN 9780415497701
  11. ^"Philosopher Art Critic Arthur C. Danto".VEERY JOURNAL.RetrievedSeptember 24,2020.
  12. ^abAda gian, Thomas."The Definition of Art",The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,London, Oct 23, 2007.
  13. ^Ross, Stephen David(1984).Art and its Significance.SUNY Press. p. 469.ISBN0-87395-764-4.Note: Ross also refers to Dickie's bookArt and the Aesthetic(Cornell University Press, 1974).
  14. ^Danto, Arthur (2014).Remarks on Art and Philosophy.New York: Acadia Summer Arts Program ASAP available through D.A.P./Distributed Art Publishers. pp. 113–114.ISBN978-0-9797642-6-4.
  15. ^The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art.By Arthur Danto. Columbia Univ Press. 1986. Page 1.
  16. ^The Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art.By Arthur Danto. Columbia Univ Press. 1986. Page 4.
  17. ^Cloweny, David W. (December 21, 2009)."Arthur Danto".Rowan university. Archived fromthe originalon December 27, 2009.RetrievedDecember 21,2009.
  18. ^Danto, Arthur Coleman(1998).After the end of art: contemporary art and the pale of history.Princeton University Press. p. 47.ISBN0-691-00299-1.As quoted by Professor David W. Cloweny on his website.[1]Archived2009-12-27 at theWayback Machine
  19. ^"Awards".The College Art Association.RetrievedOctober 11,2010.
  20. ^Danto, Arthur C. (2015).Danto on Scully.Dap-distributed Art.ISBN978-3-7757-3963-4.
  21. ^Hoving, Thomas (July 11, 2004)."The Man Who Makes a Ruckus of New York".The New York Times.ISSN0362-4331.Archived fromthe originalon May 28, 2015.RetrievedMarch 11,2022.
  22. ^from: Danto, Arthur, Juli Cho Bailer "Karen LaMonte:Absence Adorned. "Tacoma, WA: Museum of Glass, International Center for Contemporary Art, (2005)

Further reading[edit]

External links[edit]