Jump to content

Critical realism (philosophy of the social sciences)

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Critical realismis aphilosophical approach to understanding science,and in particular social science, initially developed byRoy Bhaskar(1944–2014). It specifically opposes forms ofempiricismandpositivismby viewing science as concerned with identifying causalmechanisms.In the last decades of the twentieth century it also stood against various forms ofpostmodernismandpoststructuralismby insisting on the reality of objective existence. In contrast to positivism'smethodologicalfoundation, and poststructuralism'sepistemologicalfoundation, critical realism insists that (social) science should be built from an explicitontology.Critical realism is one of a range of types ofphilosophical realism,as well as forms of realism advocated within social science such as analytic realism[1]andsubtle realism.[2][3][page needed]

Contemporary critical realism[edit]

Overview[edit]

Bhaskar developed a generalphilosophy of sciencethat he described as transcendental realism and a special philosophy of the human sciences that he called critical naturalism. The two terms were combined by other authors to form the umbrella term critical realism.[4]

Transcendental realismattempts to establish that in order for scientific investigation to take place, the object of that investigation must have real, manipulable, internal mechanisms that can beactualizedto produce particular outcomes. This is what we do when we conduct experiments. This stands in contrast to empiricist scientists' claim that all scientists can do is observe the relationship betweencause and effectand impose meaning. Whilst empiricism, and positivism more generally, locate causal relationships at the level of events, critical realism locates them at the level of the generative mechanism, arguing that causal relationships are irreducible to empiricalconstant conjunctionsofDavid Hume's doctrine; in other words, a constant conjunctive relationship between events is neither sufficient nor even necessary to establish a causal relationship.[5][page needed]

The implication of this is that science should be understood as an ongoing process in which scientists improve the concepts they use to understand the mechanisms that they study. It should not, in contrast to the claim of empiricists, be about the identification of a coincidence between a postulated independent variable and dependent variable.Positivismandnaive falsificationismare also rejected on the grounds that a mechanism may exist but either a) go unactivated, b) be activated, but not perceived, or c) be activated, but counteracted by other mechanisms, which results in its having unpredictable effects. Thus, non-realisation of a posited mechanism cannot (in contrast to the claim of some positivists) be taken to signify its non-existence. Falsificationism can be viewed at the statement level (naive falsificationism) or at the theorem level (more common in practice). In this way, the two approaches can be reconciled to some extent.[citation needed]

Critical naturalismargues that the transcendental realist model of science is equally applicable to both the physical and the human worlds. However, it argues, when we study the human world we are studying something fundamentally different from the physical world and must, therefore, adapt our strategy to studying it. Critical naturalism, therefore, prescribes social scientific methods which seek to identify the mechanisms producing social events, but with a recognition that these are in a much greater state of flux than those of the physical world (as human structures change much more readily than those of, say, a leaf). In particular, we must understand that human agency is made possible by social structures that themselves require the reproduction of certain actions/pre-conditions. Further, the individuals that inhabit these social structures are capable of consciously reflecting upon, and changing, the actions that produce them—a practice that is in part facilitated by social scientific research.[citation needed]

Critical realism has become an influential movement in Britishsociologyandsocial sciencein general as a reaction to, and reconciliation ofpostmoderncritiques.[3][page needed]

Developments[edit]

Since Bhaskar made the first big steps in popularising the theory of critical realism in the 1970s, it has become one of the major strands of social scientific method, rivalling positivism/empiricism, andpost-structuralism/relativism/interpretivism.[6][7][8]

After his development of critical realism, Bhaskar went on to develop a philosophical system he calls dialectical critical realism, which is most clearly outlined in his weighty book,Dialectic: The Pulse of Freedom.

An accessible introduction to Bhaskar's writings was written byAndrew Collier.Andrew Sayerhas written accessible texts on critical realism in social science. Danermark et al. have also produced an accessible account.Margaret Archeris associated with this school, as is theecosocialistwriter Peter Dickens.

David Graeberrelies on critical realism, which he understands as a form of 'heraclitean' philosophy, emphasizing flux and change over stable essences, in his anthropological book on the concept of value,Toward an anthropological theory of value: the false coin of our own dreams.

Recently, attention has turned to the challenge of implementing critical realism in applied social research, including its use in studying organizations.[9][page needed]). Other authors (Fletcher 2016,[10]Parr 2015,[11]Bunt 2018,[12]Hoddy 2018[13]) have discussed which specific research methodologies and methods are conducive (or not) to research guided by critical realism as a philosophy of science.

Critical realist meta-theories[edit]

At its core, critical realism offers a theory of being and existence (ontology), but it takes a more open position in relation to the theory of knowledge (epistemology). As a result, a wide range of approaches have developed that seek to offer a framework for social research. Because they are not theories in specific disciplines nor theories relating to specific aspects of society, these approaches are generally known as 'meta-theories'.[14][page needed]Critical realist meta-theories include: the transformational model of social activity,[15][page needed]the morphogenetic approach,[16][page needed]Cambridge social ontology,[17][page needed]criticaldiscourse analysis,[18][page needed]cultural political economy,[19][page needed]critical realist feminism,[20][page needed]and critical realist Marxism.[21][page needed]

The morphogenetic approach[edit]

The morphogenetic approach is a critical realist framework for analysing social change originally developed byMargaret Archerin her textSocial Origins of Educational Systems[22][page needed]and systematised in a trilogy of social theory texts,Culture and Agency(1988),Realist Social Theory(1995), andBeing Human(2000).[according to whom?]The approach was developed primarily as a critical realist response to thestructure-agencyproblem in which "we are simultaneously free and constrained and we also have some awareness of it".[23][This quote needs a citation]At the centre of Archer's answer to this problem is 'analytical dualism', which entails an analytical separation of structure and agency so that the interaction between them can be studied and modelled by researchers; on this basis, Archer rejects alternative approaches that 'conflate' structure and agency into the single concept of 'practice', primarily directing her critique atGiddens'structuration theory.[according to whom?]Archer extends the notion of analytical dualism to the distinction between "the material and the ideational aspects of social life",[24][This quote needs a citation]identifying 'culture' as a third fundamental aspect of society, alongside structure and agency. Therefore, the analysis of social change depends on modelling structure (S), agency (A), and culture (C), so that "social life comes in a SAC – always and everywhere".[25][This quote needs a citation]These concepts form the basis for the 'morphogenetic cycle', which splits social change into three processes: [T1]conditioning →[T2-T3]interaction→ [T4]elaboration:

  • At T1, agents (as individuals and as groups) are conditioned by the social structure and cultural system.
  • From T2 to T3, agents act, react, and interact
  • At T4, the social structure and cultural system are changed (morphogenesis) or maintained (morphostasis).[citation needed]

The morphogenetic approach has been advanced by Douglas Porpora, whoseReconstructing Sociologysought to introduce morphogenetic critical realism into the mainstream of American sociology.[26]Before becoming explicitly aligned with the morphogenetic approach and critical realism, Porpora published two papers on the nature of culture and social structure that later had a major influence on morphogenetic critical realism.[27]

Cambridge social ontology[edit]

Cambridge social ontology is an approach toontologythat is primarily associated with the work of philosopherTony Lawson.[28]The approach is centred on the Cambridge Social Ontology Group and its weekly Realist Workshop hosted by theUniversity of Cambridgeand led by Lawson.[29]While the group subscribes to critical realism, it identifies its aims with the study of ontology more generally rather than a necessary allegiance with the critical realist philosophy.[30]At the heart of the Cambridge approach is a theory of social positioning in which any social system creates roles (or 'places' or 'slots') that are occupied by individuals.[31][page needed]Each of these roles is attached to a series of rights and obligations; for example, one of the rights of a university lecturer is the right to use a university library and one of their obligations to deliver lectures.[32]These rights and obligations interlock to form social structures, so that the rights of an individual in one social position usually correspond with the obligations of an individual in another; for example, the rights of the lecturer might correspond to the obligations of a librarian.[32]In some cases, it is not individuals that occupy these social positions but 'communities', which are defined as "an identifiable, restricted and relatively enduring coherent grouping of people who share some set of concerns".[33][This quote needs a citation]It is important to stress that these communities can exist at a wide range of scales, they are not necessarily attached to a particular geographical space, and they can overlap and nest in various complex ways. Therefore, individuals sit within social systems by occupying a role, and they sit within communities by sharing in the community's interests in some way. A final crucial concept of the Cambridge social ontology approach is the notion of 'collective practices': a collective practice is a way of proceeding that (implicitly) bears the status of being (collectively) accepted within a community.[34]In other words, collective practices are common ways of acting in any given situation that are reinforced through conformity, such as the forming of queues to pay for goods in stores or the etiquette of a particular game or sport.[citation needed]

Critical discourse analysis[edit]

Discourse analysisis the analysis of texts and other meaningful signs with the purpose of understanding and/or explaining social phenomena.Criticaldiscourse analysis (CDA) is primarily concerned with analysing the relationship betweendiscourseand social relations of power in any given context.[35]In contrast topost-structuralistandpostmodernistapproaches to discourse analysis (such as theEssex school), CDA relies on philosophical distinctions between discourse and other aspects of reality, especially insisting on the relative independence of power relations, material existence and individual agency.[36][37]While not all CDA explicitly ascribes to critical realism (see, for example the work ofRuth WodakorTeun van Dijk), a critical realist ontology provides philosophical underpinnings for the social distinctions inherent to its approach to analysis.[35]The main proponent of a critical realist approach to CDA isNorman Fairclough,whose philosophical underpinnings shifted[according to whom?]from aFoucauldianperspective in his 1992 bookDiscourse and Social Change[38][page needed]to an explicitly critical realist approach in his 1999 collaboration with Lillian ChouliarakiDiscourse in Late Modernity.[39][page needed]Fairclough has subsequently published work developing the critical realist foundations of his version of CDA, particularly in collaboration with hisLancaster UniversitycolleaguesAndrew SayerandBob Jessop.[40][35]Fairclough explains how the main concepts oftranscendental realismunderpin his approach to the analysis of texts. Firstly, there is a distinction between the knowledge (the 'transitive dimension') and that which knowledge is about (the 'intransitive dimension'); this underpins the CDA distinction between discourse and other aspects of reality. Secondly, there is the distinction between experienced events (the 'empirical'), events themselves (the 'actual'), and the underlying mechanisms that give rise to events (the 'real'); this underpins the distinction between the reading of a text (the empirical), the text itself (the actual) and the causal structures underpinning the text's social effects (the real).[41][page needed]While these critical realist distinctions are not commonly used in the empirical application of Fairlcough's CDA, they are fundamental to the underlying social theory that justifies its application. More recently, other theorists have further developed CDA's critical realist underpinnings by focusing on the distinction betweenstructure and agency,[42]the distinction between discourse and 'non-discourse',[43]and the concept of social practices.[44]

Cultural political economy[edit]

Long-term collaboratorsNgai-Ling SumandBob Jessopinitially developed 'cultural political economy' (CPE) in a forum of the journalNew Political Economy,responding to the strict disciplinarity of existing approaches to political economy.[45]CPE also has roots in Jessop's seminal collaboration with Norman Fairclough and Andrew Sayer, which outlined a critical realist approach to 'semiosis', the inter-subjective production of meaning.[46][47]CPE is most extensively outlined in Sum and Jessop's 2013 bookCultural Political Economy,where critical realism and the strategic-relational approach are identified as the twin foundations of the approach.[48][page needed]These foundations lead to a central distinction at the heart of CPE between the 'semiotic and structural aspects of social life'. The 'semiotic' entails (a) the process by which individuals come to understand, apprehend, and make sense of the natural and social world, and (b) the process by which people (individually and in groups) come to create meaning through communication and signification, especially (though not exclusively) through the formation and use of language.[48][page needed]The semiotic is held to be foundational to all social relations and causally efficacious, so that it is both a part of social relations and a causal force in its own right. For the 'structural' aspects of social life, Sum and Jessop adopt the phrase 'structuration' fromAnthony Giddens,but reject his broader approach because of its atemporality and its conflation of agents and their actions.[48][page needed]In CPE, as in all critical realist meta-theories, social structure is held to be socially constructed, embedded in semiosis, but also not reducible to those semiotic processes, having its own material existence in social institutions, the actions of individuals, and the physical world.[47]Jessop explains that 'semiotic' and 'structural' aspects of social life change over time through three evolutionary mechanisms:[47](i) variation - there is constantvariationin human practices and social arrangements, but especially at times of crisis; (ii) selection - some practices, semiotic constructions, and structural arrangements areselected,especially as the possible routes to recovery from a crisis; (iii) retention - from the selected arrangements and practices, those that prove to be effective are retained, especially when they help overcome a crisis.[48][page needed]It is important to note that this process of variation-selection-retention, is not a functionalist account in which society is continuously 'improving', because the process is shaped by the strategies of individual agents and social structures of (unequal) power.[citation needed]

Critical realist Marxism[edit]

A development of Bhaskar's critical realism lies at the ontological root of some contemporary streams of Marxist political and economic theory.[49][page needed][50][page needed]These authors consider that realist philosophy described by Bhaskar inA Realist Theory of Scienceis compatible with Marx's work in that it differentiates between an intransitive reality, which exists independently of human knowledge of it, and the socially produced world of science and empirical knowledge. This dualist logic is present in the Marxian theory of ideology, according to which social reality may be very different from its empirically observable surface appearance. Notably,Alex Callinicoshas argued for a 'critical realist' ontology in the philosophy of social science and explicitly acknowledges Bhaskar's influence (while also rejecting the latter's 'spiritualist turn' in his later work).[51]The relationship between critical realist philosophy and Marxism has also been discussed in an article co-authored by Bhaskar and Callinicos and published in theJournal of Critical Realism.[52]

Disciplinary applications[edit]

Economics[edit]

Heterodox economists likeTony Lawson,Lars Pålsson Syll,Frederic LeeorGeoffrey Hodgsonhave used the ideas of critical realism in economics, especially the dynamic idea of macro-micro interaction.

According to critical realist economists, the central aim of economic theory is to provide explanations in terms of hidden generative structures. This position combinestranscendental realismwith a critique ofmainstream economics.It argues that mainstream economics (i) relies excessively on deductivist methodology, (ii) embraces an uncritical enthusiasm for formalism, and (iii) believes in strong conditional predictions in economics despite repeated failures.

The world that mainstream economists study is the empirical world. But according to critical realists this world is "out of phase" (Lawson) with the underlyingontologyof economic regularities. The mainstream view is thus a limited reality because empirical realists presume that the objects of inquiry are solely "empirical regularities" —that is, objects and events at the level of the experienced.

The critical realist views the domain of real causal mechanisms as the appropriate object of economic science, whereas the positivist view is that the reality is exhausted in empirical, i.e. experienced reality. Tony Lawson argues that economics ought to embrace a "social ontology" to include the underlying causes of economic phenomena.

Ecological economics[edit]

The Britishecological economistClive Spashholds the opinion that critical realism offers a thorough basis—as a philosophy of science—for the theoretical foundation of ecological economics.[53][54][page needed]He therefore uses a critical realist lens for conducting research in (ecological) economics.

However, also other scholars base ecological economics on a critical realist foundation,[55][page needed]such as Leigh Price fromRhodes University.[56][page needed]

Ecology, climate change and environmental sustainability[edit]

Critical realism's implications forecology,climate changeandenvironmental sustainabilitywere explored by Roy Bhaskar and others in their 2010 bookInterdisciplinarity and Climate Change: Transforming Knowledge and Practice for Our Global Future.[57][page needed]Nordicecophilosopherssuch as Karl Georg Høyer,Sigmund Kvaløy Setrengand Trond Gansmo Jakobsen saw the value of critical realism as a basis for the approach to ecology popularized by the Norwegian philosopherArne Næss,versions of which are sometimes calleddeep ecology.[according to whom?]Roy Bhaskar, Petter Næss, and Karl Høyer collaborated on an edited volume entitledEcophilosophy in a World of Crisis: Critical Realism and the Nordic Contributions.[relevant?][58][page needed]Zimbabwean-born ecophilosopher Leigh Price has used critical realism to develop a philosophy for ecology that she callsdeep naturalism,and she has argued for acommon-senseapproach to climate change and environmental management.[59]She also has used Bhaskar's critical realist ontology to arrive at a definition ofecological resilienceas "the process by which the internal complexity of an ecosystem and its coherence as a whole – stemming from the relative 'richness' or 'modularity' of emergent structures and behaviours/growth/life-history of species – results in the inter-dependencies of its components or their binding as totalities such that the identity of the ecosystem tends to remain intact, despite intrinsic and/or extrinsic entropic forces".[60]Other academics in this field who have worked with critical realism include Jenneth Parker, Research Director at Schumaker Institute for Sustainable Systems[61][page needed]and Sarah Cornell, Associate Professor atStockholm Resilience Centre.[citation needed]

International relations[edit]

Since 2000, critical realist philosophy has also been increasingly influential in the field of international relations (IR) theory. In 2011, Iver B. Neumann said it was "almost all the rage" among those IR scholars who are concerned with questions of philosophy of science.[62]Bob Jessop,Colin Wight, Milja Kurki, Jonathan Joseph and Hidemi Suganami have all published major works on the utility of beginning IR research from a critical realist social ontology—an ontology they all credit Roy Bhaskar with originating.[63][full citation needed]

Education[edit]

Critical realism (CR) offers a framework that can be used to approach complex questions at the interface between educational theory and educational practice. Nevertheless, CR is not a theory but a philosophical approach intended to under-labour for social science research. As a meta-theory, it does not explain any social phenomenon. Instead, the processes and techniques of the discipline, in this case, education, will provide the means for translating CR principles into a substantive study. This means that for any study framed under a CR approach, there is a need to choose a social theory (that shares a realist ontology) that explains why things are the way they are rather than some other way. As in the different disciplines described above, in educational research under a CR approach, the overall aim is to explain the educational phenomena in terms of the hidden generative mechanisms that make the events we observe happen. Rebecca Eynon of theOxford Internet Institutebelieves that when investigating issues in the field ofeducational technologyit is fundamental to address the real problems that as she argues, relate to the more profound and most of the time, imperceptible structural issues that constrain technology use. In the field of educational technology, particularly when exploring how technology is used or appropriated by teachers and students, an understanding of the social world as complex and multi-layered is helpful. Clive Lawson of the Cambridge Social Ontology Group has addressed the topic of technology from a CR perspective. The bookIsolation and Technology(2017) sets out a persuasive 'ontology of technology' and applies this perspective to explain the causal powers of technology, which for educational purposes is highly relevant. His main argument is that technology has the power to enlarge human capabilities but only if the technology/artefact is enrolled in the network of interdependencies in a particular system. He suggests a conception of technical activity "as that activity that harnesses the causal capacities and powers of material artefacts in order to extend human capabilities" (p. 109).[citation needed]

David Scott has written extensively about CR and education. In his bookEducation, Epistemology and Critical Realism(2010), he argues for a need to pay greater attention to the meta-theories which underpin educational research. An important issue for educational research, Scott argues, is the relationship between structure and agency. The work ofMargaret Archer[64][page needed]uses the morphogenetic cycle (explained in one of the sections above) as an analytical tool that allows the researcher to explore the interplay between structure and agency at any given moment in time. She uses analytical dualism, a methodological manoeuvre that helps, only for the sake of analysis, to separate structure from agency to explore their interplay at a particular moment in time. The latter was utilised by Robert Archer in his bookEducation Policy and Realist Social Theory(2002).[65][page needed]

Health[edit]

Critical realism has been used widely within health research in several different ways, including (i) informing methodological decisions, (ii) understanding the causes of health and illness, and (iii) informing ways of improving health—whether in healthcare programmes or public health promotion.[citation needed]

In a similar pattern to that seen in other fields, researchers studying health and illness have used critical realism to orient their methodological decisions.[citation needed]Critical realism has been argued to represent a philosophical approach for health sciences that is alternative and preferable to the empirical emphasis within positivism and the relativist emphasis within constructivism.[66][full citation needed]Comparable arguments are made in a range of fields such as the sociology of health and illness,[67][full citation needed][68][full citation needed]mental health research,[69][full citation needed]and nursing.[70][full citation needed]In the view of Wiltshire, use of critical realism to orient methodological decisions helps to encourage interdisciplinary health research by disrupting long-standing qualitative-quantitative divides between disciplinary traditions.[71][full citation needed]Critical realism has also been discussed in comparison to alternatives within health and rehabilitation science; in this area, DeForge and Shaw concluded that, "critical realists tend to forefront ontological considerations and focus on the hidden, taken-for-granted structures from 'the domain of the real'."[72][full citation needed]One significant methodological implication within health research has been the introduction of evaluation frameworks that are underpinned by critical realist ideas.[73][full citation needed]Evaluation research is important for healthcare research in particular because new health-related interventions and programmes need to be assessed for effectiveness. Clark and colleagues summarise the contribution of critical realism in this domain by claiming that it is useful for

(1) understanding complex outcomes, (2) optimizing interventions, and (3) researching biopsychosocial pathways. Such questions are central to evidence-based practice, chronic disease management, and population health.[74][full citation needed]

In a recent presentation, Alderson positions critical realism as a toolkit of practical ideas that helps researchers to extend and clarify their analyses.[75][full citation needed]

Research that has tried to better understand the causes of health and illness have also turned to critical realism.[citation needed]Scambler has applied sociology to the understanding of medicine, health and illness, where he presents the role of class relations and political power in reproducing and exacerbating health inequalities.[76][full citation needed][77][full citation needed][78][full citation needed]Other research into the social determinants of health has drawn on critical realism in understanding, for example, healthcare inequalities,[79][full citation needed]the rural determinants of health,[80][full citation needed]and the non-determinant causal relationship between poor housing and illness.[81][full citation needed]Others have found critical realism useful in seeking an appropriate social theory of health determination through the complex pathways and mechanisms that come to impact health and illness.[82][full citation needed]As well, critical realism has been used to advance an account of the causes of mental ill-health.[83][full citation needed]

Critical realism has also been used in health research to inform ways of improving health—whether in healthcare programmes or public health promotion.[citation needed]Clark and colleagues argue critical realism can help to understand and evaluate heart health programmes, noting that their approach "embraces measurement of objective effectiveness but also examines the mechanisms, organizational and contextual-related factors causing these outcomes."[74][full citation needed]It has also been used as an explanatory framework regarding health decisions, such as the use of home-dialysis for patients with chronic kidney disease.[84][full citation needed]Another useful example in the context of nursing practice argues that critical realism offers a philosophy that is a natural fit with human and health science enquiry, including nursing.[85][full citation needed]At the level of public health, Connelly has strongly advocated for critical realist ideas, concluding that "for health promotion theory and practice to make a difference an engagement with critical realism is now long overdue."[86][full citation needed]Critical realism is also applied in empirical studies, such as ethnographic study in Nigeria arguing that understanding the underlying mechanisms associated with smoking in different societies will enable effective implementation of tobacco control policies that work in various settings.[87][full citation needed]

See also[edit]

References[edit]

  1. ^Altheide, D. L., and Johnson, J. M.(1994). Criteria for assessing interpretive validity in qualitative research. In: N. K. Denzin and Y. S. Lincoln (eds),Handbook of Qualitative ResearchFirst edition, (pp. 485–499).Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.
  2. ^Hammersley, M. (1992). Ethnography and realism. In What's Wrong with Ethnography? (pp. 43–56). London: Routledge.
  3. ^abMadill, Anna (2012) 'Realism', in Lisa M. Given (ed.)The SAGE Encyclopedia of Qualitative Research Methods,Thousand Oaks NJ, Sage.[page needed]
  4. ^Bhaskar, Roy (2010).Reclaiming reality: a critical introduction to contemporary philosophy.London: Routledge. p. 190.ISBN978-0-203-84331-4.OCLC712652144.
  5. ^Creswell, John W.; Creswell, J. David (2 January 2018).Research design: qualitative, quantitative, and mixed methods approaches(Fifth ed.). Thousand Oaks, California.ISBN9781506386706.OCLC1004576152.{{cite book}}:CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)[page needed]
  6. ^"The Impact of Roy Bhaskar and Critical Realism on International Relations".E-International Relations.Retrieved2018-06-19.
  7. ^"Roy Bhaskar: Philosopher whose school of critical realism challenged".The Independent.Retrieved2018-06-19.
  8. ^Graeber, David (2014-12-04)."Roy Bhaskar obituary".The Guardian.Retrieved2018-06-19.
  9. ^Edwards, Paul K.; O'Mahoney, Joe; Vincent, Steve (2014).Studying Organizations Using Critical Realism: A Practical Guide.Oxford: Oxford University Press.ISBN978-0-19-966553-2.[page needed]
  10. ^Fletcher, Amber J. (2016). "Applying critical realism in qualitative research: methodology meets method".International Journal of Social Research Methodology.20(2): 181–194.doi:10.1080/13645579.2016.1144401.S2CID147258771.
  11. ^Parr, Sadie (2015)."Integrating critical realist and feminist methodologies: ethical and analytical dilemmas"(PDF).International Journal of Social Research Methodology(Submitted manuscript).8(2): 193–207.doi:10.1080/13645579.2013.868572.S2CID53051718.
  12. ^Bunt, Sarah (2018). "Critical realism and grounded theory: Analysing the adoption outcomes for disabled children using the retroduction framework".Qualitative Social Work.17(2): 176–194.doi:10.1177/1473325016664572.S2CID151878799.
  13. ^Hoddy, Eric (2018)."Critical realism in empirical research: employing techniques from Grounded theory methodology"(PDF).International Journal of Social Research Methodology.22:111–124.doi:10.1080/13645579.2018.1503400.S2CID149952268.
  14. ^Archer, Margaret, ed. (2013).Social Morphogenesis.Springer Netherlands.ISBN978-94-007-6127-8.[page needed]
  15. ^Bhaskar, Roy (2015).The possibility of naturalism: a philosophical critique of the contemporary human sciences(Fourth ed.). London.ISBN978-1-138-79889-2.OCLC872522672.{{cite book}}:CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)[page needed]
  16. ^Archer, Margaret, ed. (2013).Social Morphogenesis.Springer Netherlands.ISBN978-94-007-6127-8.[page needed]
  17. ^Pratten, Stephen, ed. (2015).Social Ontology and Modern Economics.New York: Routledge.ISBN978-1-317-70390-7.OCLC891449934.[page needed]
  18. ^Chouliaraki, Lilie; Fairclough, Norman (1999).Discourse in late modernity: rethinking critical discourse analysis.Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.ISBN0-7486-1082-0.OCLC44013742.[page needed]
  19. ^Sum, Ngai-Ling; Jessop, Bob (2005).Towards a cultural political economy: putting culture in its place in political economy.Cheltenham, UK.ISBN1-84542-036-5.OCLC58454749.{{cite book}}:CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)[page needed]
  20. ^van Ingen, Michiel; Grohmann, Steph; Gunnarsson, Lena (2020).Critical realism, feminism, and gender: a reader.Abingdon, Oxon.ISBN978-1-315-11213-8.OCLC1135913463.{{cite book}}:CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)[page needed]
  21. ^Brown, Andrew; Fleetwood, Steve; Roberts, John Michael, eds. (2002).Critical realism and Marxism.London: Routledge.ISBN0-203-29922-1.OCLC56566655.[page needed]
  22. ^Archer, Margaret (2013-03-05).Social Origins of Educational Systems.Routledge.doi:10.4324/9780203584002.ISBN978-0-203-58400-2.[page needed]
  23. ^Archer, Margaret S. (1995).Realist Social Theory: The Morphogenetic Approach.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.ISBN978-0-521-48176-2.[page needed]
  24. ^Archer, Margaret S. (1996).Culture and Agency: The Place of Culture in Social Theory(2 ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.ISBN978-0-521-56441-0.[page needed]
  25. ^Archer, Margaret, ed. (2013).Social Morphogenesis.Springer Netherlands.ISBN978-94-007-6127-8.[page needed]
  26. ^Archer, Margaret S. (2016-08-07)."Reconstructing Sociology: The Critical Realist Approach".Journal of Critical Realism.15(4): 425–431.doi:10.1080/14767430.2016.1191809.ISSN1476-7430.S2CID147762206.
  27. ^Porpora, Douglas V.; Morgan, Jamie (2020-10-19)."American sociology, realism, structure and truth: an interview with Douglas V. Porpora".Journal of Critical Realism.19(5): 522–544.doi:10.1080/14767430.2020.1782708.ISSN1476-7430.
  28. ^Porpora, Douglas (2016)."Response to Tony Lawson: Sociology Versus Economics and Philosophy".Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour.46(4): 420–425.doi:10.1111/jtsb.12130.ISSN1468-5914.
  29. ^"Cambridge Social Ontology".csog.econ.cam.ac.uk.Retrieved2021-01-22.
  30. ^Lawson, Tony (2009-09-13)."Cambridge social ontology: an interview with Tony Lawson".Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics.2(1): 100–122.doi:10.23941/ejpe.v2i1.26.ISSN1876-9098.
  31. ^"The Nature of Social Reality: Issues in Social Ontology".Routledge & CRC Press.Retrieved2021-01-22.[page needed]
  32. ^abLawson, Tony (2016)."Comparing Conceptions of Social Ontology: Emergent Social Entities and/or Institutional Facts?".Journal for the Theory of Social Behaviour.46(4): 359–399.doi:10.1111/jtsb.12126.ISSN1468-5914.
  33. ^"The Nature of Social Reality: Issues in Social Ontology".Routledge & CRC Press.Retrieved2021-01-22.[page needed]
  34. ^"Cambridge Social Ontology - Conception of Social Ontology"(PDF).Archived(PDF)from the original on 2021-01-29.
  35. ^abcFairclough, Norman (2005-06-01)."Peripheral Vision: Discourse Analysis in Organization Studies: The Case for Critical Realism".Organization Studies.26(6): 915–939.doi:10.1177/0170840605054610.ISSN0170-8406.S2CID144219030.
  36. ^Newman, Jack (2020-10-19)."Critical realism, critical discourse analysis, and the morphogenetic approach".Journal of Critical Realism.19(5): 433–455.doi:10.1080/14767430.2020.1758986.ISSN1476-7430.S2CID219481489.Archived fromthe originalon 20 May 2020.
  37. ^Laclau, Ernesto; Bhaskar, Roy (1998-07-12)."Discourse Theory vs Critical Realism".Alethia.1(2): 9–14.doi:10.1558/aleth.v1i2.9.ISSN0711-3625.
  38. ^"Discourse and Social Change | Wiley".Wiley.Retrieved2021-01-28.[page needed]
  39. ^Chouliaraki, Lilie; Fairclough, Norman (1999).Discourse in late modernity: rethinking critical discourse analysis.Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.ISBN0-7486-1082-0.OCLC44013742.[page needed]
  40. ^Fairclough, Norman; Jessop, Bob; Sayer, Andrew (2002-07-15)."Critical Realism and Semiosis".Alethia.5(1): 2–10.doi:10.1558/aleth.v5i1.2.ISSN0711-3625.S2CID8535904.
  41. ^Chouliaraki, Lilie; Fairclough, Norman (1999).Discourse in late modernity: rethinking critical discourse analysis.Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.ISBN0-7486-1082-0.OCLC44013742.[page needed]
  42. ^Flatschart, Elmar (2016-01-01)."Critical Realist Critical Discourse Analysis: A Necessary Alternative to Post-marxist Discourse Theory".Journal of Critical Realism.15(1): 21–52.doi:10.1080/14767430.2015.1118588.ISSN1476-7430.S2CID146508384.
  43. ^Banta, Benjamin (2012-04-23)."Analysing discourse as a causal mechanism".European Journal of International Relations.19(2): 379–402.doi:10.1177/1354066111428970.S2CID146918607.
  44. ^Newman, Jack (2020-10-19)."Critical realism, critical discourse analysis, and the morphogenetic approach".Journal of Critical Realism.19(5): 433–455.doi:10.1080/14767430.2020.1758986.ISSN1476-7430.S2CID219481489.
  45. ^Jessop, Bob; Sum, Ngai-Ling (2001-03-01)."Pre-disciplinary and Post-disciplinary Perspectives".New Political Economy.6(1): 89–101.doi:10.1080/13563460020027777.ISSN1356-3467.S2CID58930932.
  46. ^Fairclough, Norman; Jessop, Bob; Sayer, Andrew (2002-07-15)."Critical Realism and Semiosis".Alethia.5(1): 2–10.doi:10.1558/aleth.v5i1.2.ISSN0711-3625.S2CID8535904.
  47. ^abcJessop, Bob (2004-10-01)."Critical semiotic analysis and cultural political economy".Critical Discourse Studies.1(2): 159–174.doi:10.1080/17405900410001674506.ISSN1740-5904.S2CID218547365.
  48. ^abcdSum, Ngai-Ling; Jessop, Bob (2005).Towards a cultural political economy: putting culture in its place in political economy.Cheltenham, UK.ISBN1-84542-036-5.OCLC58454749.{{cite book}}:CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)[page needed]
  49. ^Marsh, D. (2002), "Marxism", in Marsh D. Stoker, G. (Eds.),Theory and Methods in Political Science,Basingstoke, Palgrave Macmillan.[page needed]
  50. ^Marsh, D, & Furlong, P. (2002), "Ontology and Epistemology in Political Science", in Marsh D. Stoker, G. (Eds.),Theory and Methods in Political Science, Basingstoke,Palgrave Macmillan.[page needed]
  51. ^Callinicos, A. (2006),The Resources of Critique,Cambridge, Polity, pp.155-158
  52. ^Bhaskar, R. Callinicos, A. (2003), 'Marxism and Critical Realism: A Debate', inJournal of Critical Realism,1.2
  53. ^Spash, Clive L. (2012-05-26). "New foundations for ecological economics".Ecological Economics.77:36–47.CiteSeerX10.1.1.634.2763.doi:10.1016/j.ecolecon.2012.02.004.ISSN0921-8009.
  54. ^Spash, Clive (2017-01-31), "Soziales, ökologisches und ökonomisches Wissen zum Synthetisierungspotenzial des Critical Realism", in Lindner, Urs; Mader, Dimitri (eds.),Critical Realism meets kritische Sozialtheorie,transcript Verlag,doi:10.14361/9783839427255-008,ISBN9783839427255[page needed]
  55. ^Spash, Clive L. (2017-04-07).Routledge handbook of ecological economics: nature and society.Abingdon, Oxon.ISBN9781317395096.OCLC982187453.{{cite book}}:CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)[page needed]
  56. ^Price, Leigh; Lotz-Sistka, Heila (2015-12-14).Critical realism, environmental learning, and social-ecological change.Lotz-Sisitka, Heila; Price, Leigh. London.ISBN9781317338475.OCLC932622677.{{cite book}}:CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)[page needed]
  57. ^Bhaskar, Roy, ed. (2010).Interdisciplinarity and Climate Change.London: Routledge.doi:10.4324/9780203855317.ISBN9781136996702.[page needed]
  58. ^Bhaskar, R., Naess, P. and Høyer, K.G. eds., 2011.Ecophilosophy in a World of Crisis: Critical Realism and the Nordic Contributions.Routledge.[page needed]
  59. ^Price, L., 2019. "A return to common-sense: why ecology needs transcendental realism".Journal of Critical Realism,18(1), pp. 31–44.doi:10.1080/14767430.2019.1580178
  60. ^Price, L., 2019. "The possibility of deep naturalism: a philosophy for ecology".Journal of Critical Realism,18(4), pp. 352–367.doi:10.1080/14767430.2019.1667169
  61. ^Parker, Jenneth (2014-03-21).Critiquing Sustainability, Changing Philosophy.Routledge.doi:10.4324/9780203095577.ISBN978-0-203-09557-7.[page needed]
  62. ^Jackson, Patrick Thaddeus (2011)The Conduct of Inquiry in International Relations,Routledge p. xiv.
  63. ^See:
    • Jessop, Bob (2007).State Power.Cambridge, England: CUP.[page needed]
    • Kurki, Milja (2008).Causation in International Relations: Reclaiming Causal Analysis.Cambridge, England: CUP.[page needed]
    • Wight, Colin (2006).Agents, Structures and International Relations: Politics as Ontology.Cambridge, England: CUP.[page needed]
    • Joseph, Jonathan (2012).The Social in the Global.Cambridge, England: CUP.[page needed]
  64. ^Archer, Margaret S. (1995-10-19).Realist Social Theory: The Morphogenetic Approach(1 ed.). Cambridge University Press.doi:10.1017/cbo9780511557675.ISBN978-0-521-48442-8.[page needed]
  65. ^Archer, Robert (2002).Education Policy and Realist Social Theory: Primary Teachers, Child-Centred Philosophy and the New Managerialism(First ed.). Routledge.doi:10.4324/9780203166536.ISBN9780203166536.[page needed]
  66. ^Cruikshank, 2012.[full citation needed]
  67. ^Williams, 1999.[full citation needed]
  68. ^Williams, 2003.[full citation needed]
  69. ^Pilgrim, 2013.[full citation needed]
  70. ^Clark et al., 2008.[full citation needed]
  71. ^Wiltshire, 2018.[full citation needed]
  72. ^DeForge and Shaw, 2011.[full citation needed]
  73. ^For example, see McEvoy and Richards, 2002.[full citation needed]and Costa and Magalhães, 2019.[full citation needed]
  74. ^abClark et al., 2007.[full citation needed]
  75. ^Alderson, Priscilla (2021).Critical Realism for Health and Illness Research: A Practical Introduction.[full citation needed]
  76. ^Scambler, Graham.Sociology, Health and the Fractured Society: A Critical Realist Account.[full citation needed]
  77. ^Scambler, 2001.[full citation needed]
  78. ^Scambler and Scambler, 2013.[full citation needed]
  79. ^Costa & Magalhães, 2020.[full citation needed]
  80. ^Reid, 2019.[full citation needed]
  81. ^Allen, 2000.[full citation needed]
  82. ^Collins et al., 2015.[full citation needed]
  83. ^Pilgrim & Rogers, 1997.[full citation needed]
  84. ^Harwood & Clark, 2012.[full citation needed]
  85. ^Williams et al., 2016.[full citation needed]
  86. ^Connelly, 2001.[full citation needed]
  87. ^Oladele et al., 2012.[full citation needed]

Further reading[edit]

  • Alderson, P. 2013. Childhoods Real and Imagined: An Introduction to childhood studies and critical realism, Volume 1. London: Routledge.
  • Alderson, P. 2021. Critical Realism for Health and Illness Research: A Practical Introduction. Bristol: Policy Press.
  • Archer, M., Bhaskar, R.,Collier, A.,Lawson, T. and Norrie, A., 1998,Critical Realism: Essential Readings,(London, Routledge).
  • Archer, R. (2002) Education Policy and Realist Social Theory, (London, Routledge).
  • Bhaskar, R., 1975 [1997],A Realist Theory of Science:2nd edition, (London, Verso).
  • Bhaskar, R., 1998,The Possibility of Naturalism: A Philosophical Critique of the Contemporary Human Sciences:Third Edition, (London, Routledge)
  • Bhaskar, R., 1993,Dialectic: The Pulse of Freedom,(London, Verso).
  • Bhaskar, Roy, Berth Danermark, and Leigh Price. Interdisciplinarity and wellbeing: a critical realist general theory of interdisciplinarity. Routledge, 2017.
  • Bhaskar, R. (2016) Enlightened Common Sense: The Philosophy of Critical Realism, edited with a preface by Hartwig, M. London: Routledge.
  • Collier, A. 1994, 'Critical Realism: An Introduction to Roy Bhaskar's Philosophy', (London, Verso).Frauley, J. and Pearce, F. (eds). 2007.Critical Realism and the Social Sciences.(Toronto and Buffalo. University of Toronto Press).
  • Danermark, B., M. Ekström, L. Jakobs & J.Ch. Karlsson,Explaining Society: An Introduction to Critical Realism in the Social Sciences.(Critical Realism: Interventions), Routledge, Abingdon 2002.
  • Hartwig, M. 2007 Dictionary of Critical Realism. London: Routledge.
  • Lopez, J. and Potter, G., 2001,After Postmodernism: An Introduction to Critical Realism,(London, The Athlone Press).
  • Maton, K., & Moore, R. (Eds.). (2010). Social realism, knowledge and the sociology of education: Coalitions of the mind. London: Continuum.
  • Næss, Petter, and Leigh Price, eds. 2016. Crisis system: A critical realist and environmental critique of economics and the economy. Routledge.
  • Price, Leigh, and Heila Lotz-Sistka, eds. 2015. Critical realism, environmental learning and social-ecological change. Routledge.
  • Sayer, A. (1992)Method in Social Science: A Realist Approach,(London, Routledge)
  • Sayer, A. (2000)Realism and Social Science,(London, Sage)

External links[edit]