Jump to content

Donkey sentence

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected fromDonkey anaphora)

Insemantics,adonkey sentenceis a sentence containing apronounwhich is semanticallyboundbut syntactically free. They are a classic puzzle informal semanticsandphilosophy of languagebecause they are fullygrammaticaland yet defy straightforward attempts to generate theirformal languageequivalents. In order to explain how speakers are able to understand them, semanticists have proposed a variety of formalisms including systems ofdynamic semanticssuch asDiscourse representation theory.Their name comes from the example sentence "Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it", in which thedonkey pronounacts as a donkey pronoun because it is semantically but not syntactically bound by the indefinitenoun phrase"a donkey". The phenomenon is known asdonkey anaphora.[a]

Examples

[edit]

The following sentences are examples of donkey sentences.

  • Omne homo habens asinum videt illum.( "Every man who owns a donkey sees it" ) —Walter Burley(1328),De puritate artis logicae tractatus longior[3][4]
  • Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it.[5]
  • If a farmer owns a donkey, he beats it.
  • Every police officer who arrested a murderer insulted him. "

Analysis of donkey sentences

[edit]

The goal offormal semanticsis to show how sentences of anatural languagesuch asEnglishcould be translated into a formal logical language, and so would then be amenable to mathematical analysis. FollowingRussell,it is typical to translateindefinite noun phrasesusing anexistential quantifier,[6] as in the following simple example from Burchardtet al:

"A woman smokes." is translated as[7]

The prototypical donkey sentence, "Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it.", requires careful consideration for adequate description (though reading "each" in place of "every" does simplify the formal analysis). The donkey pronoun in this case is the wordit.Correctly translating this sentence will require using auniversal quantifierfor the indefinite noun phrase "a donkey", rather than the expected existential quantifier.

The naive first attempt at translation given below is not a well-formed sentence, since the variableis leftfreein the predicate.[8]

It may be attempted to extend thescopeof the existential quantifier to bind the free instance of,but it still does not give a correct translation.[8]

This translation is incorrect since it is already true if there exists any object that is not a donkey: Given any object to be substituted for,substituting any non-donkey object formakes thematerial conditionaltrue (since itsantecedentis false), and so existential clause is true for every choice of.

A correct translation into first-order logic for the donkey sentence seems to be

,

indicating that indefinites must sometimes be interpreted as existential quantifiers, and other times as universal quantifiers.[8]

There is nothing wrong with donkey sentences: they are grammatically correct, they are well-formed and meaningful, and their syntax is regular. However, it is difficult to explain how donkey sentences produce their semantic results, and how those results generalize consistently with all other language use. If such an analysis were successful, it might allow a computer program to accurately translate natural language forms intological form.[9]It is unknown how natural language users agree – apparently effortlessly – on the meaning of sentences such as the examples.[citation needed]

There may be several equivalent ways of describing this process. In fact,Hans Kamp(1981) andIrene Heim(1982) independently proposed very similar accounts in different terminology, which they calleddiscourse representation theory(DRT) andfile change semantics(FCS), respectively.

Theories of donkey anaphora

[edit]

It is usual to distinguish two main kinds of theories about the semantics of donkey pronouns. The most classical proposals fall within the so-calleddescription-theoretic approach,a label that is meant to encompass all the theories that treat the semantics of these pronouns as akin to, or derivative from, the semantics ofdefinite descriptions.The second main family of proposals goes by the namedynamic theories,and they model donkey anaphora – and anaphora in general – on the assumption that the meaning of a sentence lies in its potential to change the context (understood as the information shared by the participants in a conversation).[10]

Description-theoretic approaches

[edit]

Description-theoretic approaches are theories of donkey pronouns in which definite descriptions play an important role. They were pioneered byGareth Evans's E-type approach,[11]which holds that donkey pronouns can be understood as referring terms whose reference is fixed by description.

For example, in "Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it.", the donkey pronoun "it" can be expanded as a definite description to yield "Every farmer who owns a donkey beats the donkey he/she owns." This expanded sentence can be interpreted along the lines of Russell'stheory of descriptions.[12]

Later authors have attributed an even larger role to definite descriptions, to the point of arguing that donkey pronouns have the semantics,[13][14]and even the syntax,[15]of definite descriptions. Approaches of the latter kind are usually calledD-type.

Discourse representation theory

[edit]

Donkey sentences became a major force in advancingsemanticresearch in the 1980s, with the introduction ofdiscourse representation theory(DRT). During that time, an effort was made to settle the inconsistencies which arose from the attempts to translate donkey sentences intofirst-order logic.

The solution thatDRTprovides for the donkey sentence problem can be roughly outlined as follows: The common semantic function of non-anaphoricnoun phrasesis the introduction of a newdiscourse referent,which is in turn available for the binding of anaphoric expressions. No quantifiers are introduced into the representation, thus overcoming the scope problem that the logical translations had.

Dynamic Predicate Logic

[edit]

Dynamic Predicate Logic models pronouns asfirst-order logicvariables,but allows quantifiers in aformulato bind variables in other formulae.[16]

History

[edit]

Walter Burley,a medieval scholastic philosopher, introduced donkey sentences in the context of the theory ofsuppositio,the medieval equivalent of reference theory.

Peter Geachreintroduced donkey sentences as acounterexampletoRichard Montague's proposal for a generalized formal representation ofquantificationinnatural language.[5]His example was reused byDavid Lewis(1975),[17]Gareth Evans(1977)[11]and many others, and is still quoted in recent publications.

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^Maier, Emar (20 Nov 2006)."Situations and Individuals by Paul D. Elbourne".LINGUIST List(review).17(3393).
  2. ^Barker, Chris;Shan, Chung-chieh (9 June 2008)."Donkey anaphora is in-scope binding".Semantics and Pragmatics.1(1): 1–46.doi:10.3765/sp.1.1.ISSN1937-8912.Retrieved29 December2020.
  3. ^Gualterus Burlaeus (1988).De puritate artis logicae tractatus longior.Meiner Verlag.ISBN9783787307173.
  4. ^Keith Allan(2010).Concise Encyclopedia of Semantics.Elsevier.ISBN9780080959696.
  5. ^abPeter Geach(1962).Reference and Generality.Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press – via philosophieweb0.001.free.fr/GeachRandG.pdf.
  6. ^Heim, Irene(1982).The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases(PDF)(PhD). University of Massachusetts Amherst. pp. 11–12.Retrieved29 December2020.
  7. ^Burchardt, Aljoscha; Walter, Stephan; Koller, Alexander;Kohlhase, Michael;Blackburn, Patrick; Bos, Johan."Anaphoric Pronouns".Computational Semantics 11.1.1.Saarland University.Retrieved29 December2020.
  8. ^abcBurchardt, Aljoscha; Walter, Stephan; Koller, Alexander; Kohlhase, Michael; Blackburn, Patrick; Bos, Johan."Donkey Sentences".Computational Semantics 11.1.2.Saarland University.Retrieved29 December2020.
  9. ^Knott, Alistair (2000)."An Algorithmic Framework for Specifying the Semantics of Discourse Relations"(PDF).Computational Intelligence.16(4): 501–510.doi:10.1111/0824-7935.00123.S2CID1295252.
  10. ^Elbourne, Paul (2005).Situations and individuals.MIT Press.ISBN9780262550611.
  11. ^abEvans, Gareth (September 1977). "Pronouns, Quantifiers and Relative Clauses (I)".Canadian Journal of Philosophy.7(3): 467–536.doi:10.1080/00455091.1977.10717030.S2CID146125231.
  12. ^Partee, Barbara H.(18 March 2008)."Formal Semantics and Current Problems of Semantics, Lecture 6. Kamp-Heim I. Anaphora with Indefinite Antecedents; Donkey Anaphora"(PDF).RGGU: Formal Semantics and Anaphora.University of Massachusetts. p. 9.Retrieved29 December2020.
  13. ^Cooper, Robin (1979). "The interpretation of pronouns". In Frank Heny; Helmut Schnelle (eds.).Syntax and Semantics 10: Selections from the third Gröningen roundtable.Academic Press.ISBN012613510X.
  14. ^Neale, Stephen(1990).Descriptions.The MIT Press.ISBN0262640317.
  15. ^Heim, Irene;Kratzer, Angelika(1998).Semantics in Generative Grammar.Blackwell.ISBN0631197133.
  16. ^Groenendijk, Jeroen;Stokhof, Martin(1991)."Dynamic Predicate Logic"(PDF).Linguistics and Philosophy.14:39–100.doi:10.1007/BF00628304.S2CID62551132.
  17. ^Lewis, David(1975). "Adverbs of quantification". In Keenan, Edward L. (ed.).Formal Semantics of Natural Language.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.ISBN9780511897696– via users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LewisQA.pdf.

Further reading

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^Emar Maier describes donkey pronouns as "bound but notc-commanded"in aLinguist Listreviewof Paul D. Elbourne'sSituations and Individuals(MIT Press,2006).[1]Barkerand Shan define a donkey pronoun as "a pronoun that lies outside the restrictor of aquantifieror the if-clause of aconditional,yetcovarieswith somequantificationalelement inside it, usually anindefinite."[2]
  2. ^In 2007, Adrian Brasoveanu published studies of donkey pronoun analogs inHindi,and analysis of complex andmodalversions of donkey pronouns in English.
[edit]