Empiricism
Part of a series on |
Epistemology |
---|
Part ofa serieson |
Research |
---|
Philosophy portal |
Inphilosophy,empiricismis anepistemological viewwhich holds that true knowledge or justification comes only or primarily fromsensory experienceandempirical evidence.[1]It is one of several competing views within epistemology, along withrationalismandskepticism.Empiricists argue that empiricism is a more reliable method of finding the truth than purely usinglogical reasoning,because humans have cognitivebiasesand limitations which lead to errors of judgement.[2]Empiricism emphasizes the central role ofempirical evidencein the formation of ideas, rather thaninnate ideasortraditions.[3]Empiricists may argue that traditions (or customs) arise due to relations of previous sensory experiences.[4]
Historically, empiricism was associated with the "blank slate"concept (tabula rasa), according to which the human mind is "blank" at birth and develops its thoughts only through later experience.[5]
Empiricism in thephilosophy of scienceemphasizes evidence, especially as discovered inexperiments.It is a fundamental part of thescientific methodthat all hypotheses and theories must be tested against observations of the natural world rather than resting solely ona priorireasoning,intuition,orrevelation.
Empiricism, often used bynatural scientists,believes that "knowledge is based on experience" and that "knowledge is tentative and probabilistic, subject to continued revision andfalsification".[6]Empirical research, including experiments and validated measurement tools, guides the scientific method.
Etymology
[edit]The English termempiricalderives from theAncient Greekword ἐμπειρία,empeiria,which is cognate with and translates to the Latinexperientia,from which the wordsexperienceandexperimentare derived.[7]
Background
[edit]A central concept inscienceand thescientific methodis that conclusions must beempiricallybased on the evidence of the senses. Bothnaturalandsocial sciencesuse workinghypothesesthat aretestablebyobservationandexperiment.The termsemi-empiricalis sometimes used to describe theoretical methods that make use of basicaxioms,established scientific laws, and previous experimental results to engage in reasoned model building and theoretical inquiry.
Philosophical empiricists hold no knowledge to be properly inferred or deduced unless it is derived from one's sense-based experience.[8]Inepistemology(theory of knowledge) empiricism is typically contrasted withrationalism,which holds that knowledge may be derived fromreasonindependently of the senses, and in thephilosophy of mindit is often contrasted withinnatism,which holds that some knowledge and ideas are already present in the mind at birth. However, many Enlightenment rationalists and empiricists still made concessions to each other. For example, the empiricistJohn Lockeadmitted that some knowledge (e.g. knowledge of God's existence) could be arrived at throughintuitionand reasoning alone. Similarly,Robert Boyle,a prominent advocate of the experimental method, held that we also have innate ideas.[9][10]At the same time, the main continentalrationalists(Descartes,Spinoza,andLeibniz) were also advocates of the empirical "scientific method".[11][12]
History
[edit]Early empiricism
[edit]Between 600 and 200 BCE, theVaisheshikaschool of Hindu philosophy,founded by the ancient Indian philosopherKanada,acceptedperceptionandinferenceas the only two reliable sources of knowledge.[13][14][15]This is enumerated in his workVaiśeṣika Sūtra.TheCharvakaschool held similar beliefs, asserting that perception is the only reliable source of knowledge while inference obtains knowledge with uncertainty.
The earliest Western proto-empiricists were theempiric schoolof ancient Greek medical practitioners, founded in 330 BCE.[16]Its members rejected the doctrines of thedogmatic school,preferring to rely on the observation ofphantasiai(i.e., phenomena, the appearances).[17]The Empiric school was closely allied with thePyrrhonistschool of philosophy, which made the philosophical case for their proto-empiricism.
The notion oftabula rasa( "clean slate" or "blank tablet" ) connotes a view of the mind as an originally blank or empty recorder (Locke used the words "white paper" ) on which experience leaves marks. This denies that humans haveinnate ideas.The notion dates back toAristotle,c. 350 BC:
What the mind (nous) thinks must be in it in the same sense as letters are on a tablet (grammateion) which bears no actual writing (grammenon); this is just what happens in the case of the mind. (Aristotle,On the Soul,3.4.430a1).
Aristotle's explanation of how this was possible was not strictly empiricist in a modern sense, but rather based on his theory ofpotentiality and actuality,and experience of sense perceptions still requires the help of theactivenous.These notions contrasted withPlatonicnotions of the human mind as an entity that pre-existed somewhere in the heavens, before being sent down to join a body on Earth (see Plato'sPhaedoandApology,as well as others). Aristotle was considered to give a more important position to sense perception thanPlato,and commentators in the Middle Ages summarized one of his positions as "nihil in intellectu nisi prius fuerit in sensu"(Latin for" nothing in the intellect without first being in the senses ").
This idea was later developed in ancient philosophy by theStoicschool, from about 330 BCE. Stoic epistemology generally emphasizes that the mind starts blank, but acquires knowledge as the outside world is impressed upon it.[18]The doxographerAetiussummarizes this view as "When a man is born, the Stoics say, he has the commanding part of his soul like a sheet of paper ready for writing upon."[19]
Islamic Golden Age and Pre-Renaissance (5th to 15th centuries CE)
[edit]During theMiddle Ages(from the 5th to the 15th century CE) Aristotle's theory oftabula rasawas developed byIslamic philosophersstarting withAl Farabi(c. 872– c. 951 CE), developing into an elaborate theory byAvicenna(c. 980 – 1037 CE)[20]and demonstrated as athought experimentbyIbn Tufail.[21]For Avicenna (Ibn Sina), for example, thetabula rasais a pure potentiality that is actualized througheducation,and knowledge is attained through "empirical familiarity with objects in this world from which one abstracts universal concepts" developed through a "syllogisticmethod ofreasoningin which observations lead to propositional statements which when compounded lead to further abstract concepts ". Theintellectitself develops from amaterial intellect(al-'aql al-hayulani), which is apotentiality"that can acquire knowledge to theactive intellect(al-'aqlal-fa'il), the state of the human intellect in conjunction with the perfect source of knowledge ".[20]So the immaterial "active intellect", separate from any individual person, is still essential for understanding to occur.
In the 12th century CE, theAndalusianMuslimphilosopher and novelist Abu BakrIbn Tufail(known as "Abubacer" or "Ebu Tophail" in the West) included the theory oftabula rasaas athought experimentin hisArabic philosophical novel,Hayy ibn Yaqdhanin which he depicted the development of the mind of aferal child"from atabula rasato that of an adult, in complete isolation from society "on adesert island,through experience alone. TheLatintranslation of hisphilosophical novel,entitledPhilosophus Autodidactus,published byEdward Pocockethe Younger in 1671, had an influence onJohn Locke's formulation oftabula rasainAn Essay Concerning Human Understanding.[21]
A similarIslamic theologicalnovel,Theologus Autodidactus,was written by the Arab theologian and physicianIbn al-Nafisin the 13th century. It also dealt with the theme of empiricism through the story of a feral child on a desert island, but departed from its predecessor by depicting the development of the protagonist's mind through contact with society rather than in isolation from society.[22]
During the 13th centuryThomas Aquinasadopted intoscholasticismtheAristotelianposition that the senses are essential to the mind.Bonaventure(1221–1274), one of Aquinas' strongest intellectual opponents, offered some of the strongest arguments in favour of the Platonic idea of the mind.
Renaissance Italy
[edit]In the laterenaissancevarious writers began to question themedievalandclassicalunderstanding of knowledge acquisition in a more fundamental way. In political and historical writingNiccolò Machiavelliand his friendFrancesco Guicciardiniinitiated a new realistic style of writing. Machiavelli in particular was scornful of writers on politics who judged everything in comparison to mental ideals and demanded that people should study the "effectual truth" instead. Their contemporary,Leonardo da Vinci(1452–1519) said, "If you find from your own experience that something is a fact and it contradicts what some authority has written down, then you must abandon the authority and base your reasoning on your own findings."[23]
Significantly, an empirical metaphysical system was developed by the Italian philosopherBernardino Telesiowhich had an enormous impact on the development of later Italian thinkers, including Telesio's studentsAntonio PersioandSertorio Quattromani,his contemporariesThomas CampanellaandGiordano Bruno,and later British philosophers such asFrancis Bacon,who regarded Telesio as "the first of the moderns".[24]Telesio's influence can also be seen on the French philosophersRené DescartesandPierre Gassendi.[24]
The decidedly anti-Aristotelian and anti-clerical music theoristVincenzo Galilei(c. 1520 – 1591), father ofGalileoand the inventor ofmonody,made use of the method in successfully solving musical problems, firstly, of tuning such as the relationship of pitch to string tension and mass in stringed instruments, and to volume of air in wind instruments; and secondly to composition, by his various suggestions to composers in hisDialogo della musica antica e moderna(Florence, 1581). The Italian word he used for "experiment" wasesperimento.It is known that he was the essential pedagogical influence upon the young Galileo, his eldest son (cf. Coelho, ed.Music and Science in the Age of Galileo Galilei), arguably one of the most influential empiricists in history. Vincenzo, through his tuning research, found the underlying truth at the heart of the misunderstood myth of 'Pythagoras' hammers' (the square of the numbers concerned yielded those musical intervals, not the actual numbers, as believed), and through this and other discoveries that demonstrated the fallibility of traditional authorities, a radically empirical attitude developed, passed on to Galileo, which regarded "experience and demonstration" as thesine qua nonof valid rational enquiry.
British empiricism
[edit]British empiricism,a retrospective characterization, emerged during the 17th century as an approach toearly modern philosophyandmodern science.Although both integral to this overarching transition,Francis Bacon,in England, firstadvocated for empiricism in 1620,whereasRené Descartes,in France, laid the main groundworkupholding rationalismaround 1640. (Bacon's natural philosophy was influenced by Italian philosopherBernardino Telesioand by Swiss physicianParacelsus.)[24]Contributing later in the 17th century,Thomas HobbesandBaruch Spinozaare retrospectively identified likewise as an empiricist and a rationalist, respectively. In theEnlightenmentof the late 17th century,John Lockein England, and in the 18th century, bothGeorge Berkeleyin Ireland andDavid HumeinScotland,all became leading exponents of empiricism, hence the dominance of empiricism in British philosophy. The distinction between rationalism and empiricism was not formally made untilImmanuel Kant,in Germany,around 1780,who sought to merge the two views.[25][26]
In response to the early-to-mid-17th-century "continental rationalism",John Locke(1632–1704) proposed inAn Essay Concerning Human Understanding(1689) a very influential view wherein theonlyknowledge humans can have isa posteriori,i.e., based upon experience. Locke is famously attributed with holding the proposition that the human mind is atabula rasa,a "blank tablet", in Locke's words "white paper", on which the experiences derived from sense impressions as a person's life proceeds are written.
There are two sources of our ideas: sensation and reflection. In both cases, a distinction is made between simple and complex ideas. The former are unanalysable, and are broken down into primary and secondary qualities. Primary qualities are essential for the object in question to be what it is. Without specific primary qualities, an object would not be what it is. For example, an apple is an apple because of the arrangement of its atomic structure. If an apple were structured differently, it would cease to be an apple. Secondary qualities are the sensory information we can perceive from its primary qualities. For example, an apple can be perceived in various colours, sizes, and textures but it is still identified as an apple. Therefore, its primary qualities dictate what the object essentially is, while its secondary qualities define its attributes. Complex ideas combine simple ones, and divide into substances, modes, and relations. According to Locke, our knowledge of things is a perception of ideas that are in accordance or discordance with each other, which is very different from the quest forcertaintyofDescartes.[citation needed]
A generation later, the IrishAnglicanbishopGeorge Berkeley(1685–1753) determined that Locke's view immediately opened a door that would lead to eventualatheism.In response to Locke, he put forth in hisTreatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge(1710) an important challenge to empiricism in which thingsonlyexist either as aresultof their being perceived, or by virtue of the fact that they are an entity doing the perceiving. (For Berkeley, God fills in for humans by doing the perceiving whenever humans are not around to do it.) In his textAlciphron,Berkeley maintained that any order humans may see in nature is the language or handwriting of God.[27]Berkeley's approach to empiricism would later come to be calledsubjective idealism.[28][29]
Scottish philosopherDavid Hume(1711–1776) responded to Berkeley's criticisms of Locke, as well as other differences between early modern philosophers, and moved empiricism to a new level ofskepticism.Hume argued in keeping with the empiricist view that all knowledge derives from sense experience, but he accepted that this has implications not normally acceptable to philosophers. He wrote for example, "Locke divides all arguments into demonstrative and probable. On this view, we must say that it is only probable that all men must die or that the sun will rise to-morrow, because neither of these can be demonstrated. But to conform our language more to common use, we ought to divide arguments into demonstrations, proofs, and probabilities—by ‘proofs’ meaning arguments from experience that leave no room for doubt or opposition."[30]And,[31]
I believe the most general and most popular explication of this matter, is to say [See Mr. Locke, chapter of power.], that finding from experience, that there are several new productions in matter, such as the motions and variations of body, and concluding that there must somewhere be a power capable of producing them, we arrive at last by this reasoning at the idea of power and efficacy. But to be convinced that this explication is more popular than philosophical, we need but reflect on two very obvious principles. First, That reason alone can never give rise to any original idea, and secondly, that reason, as distinguished from experience, can never make us conclude, that a cause or productive quality is absolutely requisite to every beginning of existence. Both these considerations have been sufficiently explained: and therefore shall not at present be any farther insisted on.
— Hume, Section XIV, "Of the idea of necessary connexion", inA Treatise of Human Nature
Hume divided all of human knowledge into two categories:relations of ideasandmatters of fact(see alsoKant'sanalytic-synthetic distinction). Mathematical and logical propositions (e.g. "that the square of the hypotenuse is equal to the sum of the squares of the two sides" ) are examples of the first, while propositions involving somecontingentobservation of the world (e.g. "the sun rises in the East" ) are examples of the second. All of people's "ideas", in turn, are derived from their "impressions". For Hume, an "impression" corresponds roughly with what we call a sensation. To remember or to imagine such impressions is to have an "idea". Ideas are therefore the faint copies of sensations.[4]
Hume maintained that no knowledge, even the most basic beliefs about the natural world, can be conclusively established by reason. Rather, he maintained, our beliefs are more a result of accumulatedhabits,developed in response to accumulated sense experiences. Among his many arguments Hume also added another important slant to the debate aboutscientific method—that of theproblem of induction.Hume argued that it requiresinductive reasoningto arrive at the premises for the principle of inductive reasoning, and therefore the justification for inductive reasoning is a circular argument.[4]Among Hume's conclusions regarding the problem of induction is that there is no certainty that the future will resemble the past. Thus, as a simple instance posed by Hume, we cannot know with certainty byinductive reasoningthat the sun will continue to rise in the East, but instead come to expect it to do so because it has repeatedly done so in the past.[4]
Hume concluded that such things as belief in an external world and belief in the existence of the self were not rationally justifiable. According to Hume these beliefs were to be accepted nonetheless because of their profound basis in instinct and custom. Hume's lasting legacy, however, was the doubt that his skeptical arguments cast on the legitimacy of inductive reasoning, allowing many skeptics who followed to cast similar doubt.[citation needed]
Phenomenalism
[edit]Most of Hume's followers have disagreed with his conclusion that belief in an external world isrationallyunjustifiable, contending that Hume's own principles implicitly contained the rational justification for such a belief, that is, beyond being content to let the issue rest on human instinct, custom and habit.[32]According to an extreme empiricist theory known asphenomenalism,anticipated by the arguments of both Hume and George Berkeley, a physical object is a kind of construction out of our experiences.[33]
Phenomenalism is the view that physical objects, properties, events (whatever is physical) are reducible to mental objects, properties, events. Ultimately, only mental objects, properties, events, exist—hence the closely related termsubjective idealism.By the phenomenalistic line of thinking, to have a visual experience of a real physical thing is to have an experience of a certain kind of group of experiences. This type of set of experiences possesses a constancy and coherence that is lacking in the set of experiences of which hallucinations, for example, are a part. AsJohn Stuart Millput it in the mid-19th century, matter is the "permanent possibility of sensation".[34] Mill's empiricism went a significant step beyond Hume in still another respect: in maintaining that induction is necessary forallmeaningful knowledge including mathematics. As summarized by D.W. Hamlin:
[Mill] claimed that mathematical truths were merely very highly confirmed generalizations from experience; mathematical inference, generally conceived as deductive [anda priori] in nature, Mill set down as founded on induction. Thus, in Mill's philosophy there was no real place for knowledge based on relations of ideas. In his view logical and mathematical necessity is psychological; we are merely unable to conceive any other possibilities than those that logical and mathematical propositions assert. This is perhaps the most extreme version of empiricism known, but it has not found many defenders.[29]
Mill's empiricism thus held that knowledge of any kind is not from direct experience but an inductive inference from direct experience.[35]The problems other philosophers have had with Mill's position center around the following issues: Firstly, Mill's formulation encounters difficulty when it describes what direct experience is by differentiating only between actual and possible sensations. This misses some key discussion concerning conditions under which such "groups of permanent possibilities of sensation" might exist in the first place. Berkeley put God in that gap; the phenomenalists, including Mill, essentially left the question unanswered.
In the end, lacking an acknowledgement of an aspect of "reality" that goes beyond mere "possibilities of sensation", such a position leads to a version of subjective idealism. Questions of how floor beams continue to support a floor while unobserved, how trees continue to grow while unobserved and untouched by human hands, etc., remain unanswered, and perhaps unanswerable in these terms.[29][36]Secondly, Mill's formulation leaves open the unsettling possibility that the "gap-filling entities are purely possibilities and not actualities at all".[36]Thirdly, Mill's position, by calling mathematics merely another species of inductive inference, misapprehends mathematics. It fails to fully consider the structure and method ofmathematical science,the products of which are arrived at through an internally consistentdeductiveset of procedures which do not, either today or at the time Mill wrote, fall under the agreed meaning ofinduction.[29][36][37]
The phenomenalist phase of post-Humean empiricism ended by the 1940s, for by that time it had become obvious that statements about physical things could not be translated into statements about actual and possible sense data.[38]If a physical object statement is to be translatable into a sense-data statement, the former must be at least deducible from the latter. But it came to be realized that there is no finite set of statements about actual and possible sense-data from which we can deduce even a single physical-object statement. The translating or paraphrasing statement must be couched in terms of normal observers in normal conditions of observation.
There is, however, nofiniteset of statements that are couched in purely sensory terms and can express the satisfaction of the condition of the presence of a normal observer. According to phenomenalism, to say that a normal observer is present is to make the hypothetical statement that were a doctor to inspect the observer, the observer would appear to the doctor to be normal. But, of course, the doctor himself must be a normal observer. If we are to specify this doctor's normality in sensory terms, we must make reference to a second doctor who, when inspecting the sense organs of the first doctor, would himself have to have the sense data a normal observer has when inspecting the sense organs of a subject who is a normal observer. And if we are to specify in sensory terms that the second doctor is a normal observer, we must refer to a third doctor, and so on (also see thethird man).[39][40]
Logical empiricism
[edit]Logical empiricism (alsological positivismorneopositivism) was an early 20th-century attempt to synthesize the essential ideas of British empiricism (e.g. a strong emphasis on sensory experience as the basis for knowledge) with certain insights frommathematical logicthat had been developed byGottlob FregeandLudwig Wittgenstein.Some of the key figures in this movement wereOtto Neurath,Moritz Schlickand the rest of theVienna Circle,along withA. J. Ayer,Rudolf CarnapandHans Reichenbach.
The neopositivists subscribed to a notion of philosophy as the conceptual clarification of the methods, insights and discoveries of the sciences. They saw in the logical symbolism elaborated by Frege (1848–1925) andBertrand Russell(1872–1970) a powerful instrument that could rationally reconstruct all scientific discourse into an ideal, logically perfect, language that would be free of the ambiguities and deformations of natural language. This gave rise to what they saw as metaphysical pseudoproblems and other conceptual confusions. By combining Frege's thesis that all mathematical truths are logical with the early Wittgenstein's idea that alllogical truthsare mere linguistictautologies,they arrived at a twofold classification of all propositions: the "analytic" (a priori) and the "synthetic" (a posteriori).[41]On this basis, they formulated a strong principle of demarcation between sentences that have sense and those that do not: the so-called "verification principle".Any sentence that is not purely logical, or is unverifiable, is devoid of meaning. As a result, most metaphysical, ethical, aesthetic and other traditional philosophical problems came to be considered pseudoproblems.[42]
In the extreme empiricism of the neopositivists—at least before the 1930s—any genuinely synthetic assertion must be reducible to an ultimate assertion (or set of ultimate assertions) that expresses direct observations or perceptions. In later years, Carnap and Neurath abandoned this sort ofphenomenalismin favor of a rational reconstruction of knowledge into the language of an objective spatio-temporal physics. That is, instead of translating sentences about physical objects into sense-data, such sentences were to be translated into so-calledprotocol sentences,for example, "Xat locationYand at timeTobserves such and such ".[43]The central theses of logical positivism (verificationism, the analytic–synthetic distinction, reductionism, etc.) came under sharp attack after World War II by thinkers such asNelson Goodman,W. V. Quine,Hilary Putnam,Karl Popper,andRichard Rorty.By the late 1960s, it had become evident to most[who?]philosophers that the movement had pretty much run its course, though its influence is still significant among contemporaryanalytic philosopherssuch asMichael Dummettand otheranti-realists.
Pragmatism
[edit]In the late 19th and early 20th century, several forms ofpragmatic philosophyarose. The ideas of pragmatism, in its various forms, developed mainly from discussions betweenCharles Sanders PeirceandWilliam Jameswhen both men were at Harvard in the 1870s. James popularized the term "pragmatism", giving Peirce full credit for its patrimony, but Peirce later demurred from the tangents that the movement was taking, and redubbed what he regarded as the original idea with the name of "pragmaticism". Along with itspragmatic theory of truth,this perspective integrates the basic insights of empirical (experience-based) andrational(concept-based) thinking.
Charles Peirce (1839–1914) was highly influential in laying the groundwork for today's empiricalscientific method.[44]Although Peirce severely criticized many elements of Descartes' peculiar brand of rationalism, he did not reject rationalism outright. Indeed, he concurred with the main ideas of rationalism, most importantly the idea that rational concepts can be meaningful and the idea that rational concepts necessarily go beyond the data given by empirical observation. In later years he even emphasized the concept-driven side of the then ongoing debate between strict empiricism and strict rationalism, in part to counterbalance the excesses to which some of his cohorts had taken pragmatism under the "data-driven" strict-empiricist view.
Among Peirce's major contributions was to placeinductive reasoninganddeductive reasoningin a complementary rather than competitive mode, the latter of which had been the primary trend among the educated since David Hume wrote a century before. To this, Peirce added the concept ofabductive reasoning.The combined three forms of reasoning serve as a primary conceptual foundation for the empirically based scientific method today. Peirce's approach "presupposes that (1) the objects of knowledge are real things, (2) the characters (properties) of real things do not depend on our perceptions of them, and (3) everyone who has sufficient experience of real things will agree on the truth about them. According to Peirce's doctrine offallibilism,the conclusions of science are always tentative. The rationality of the scientific method does not depend on the certainty of its conclusions, but on its self-corrective character: by continued application of the method science can detect and correct its own mistakes, and thus eventually lead to the discovery of truth ".[45]
In his Harvard "Lectures on Pragmatism" (1903), Peirce enumerated what he called the "three cotary propositions of pragmatism" (L:cos, cotiswhetstone), saying that they "put the edge on themaxim of pragmatism".First among these, he listed the peripatetic-thomist observation mentioned above, but he further observed that this link between sensory perception and intellectual conception is a two-way street. That is, it can be taken to say that whatever we find in the intellect is also incipiently in the senses. Hence, if theories are theory-laden then so are the senses, and perception itself can be seen as a species ofabductive inference,its difference being that it is beyond control and hence beyond critique—in a word, incorrigible. This in no way conflicts with the fallibility and revisability of scientific concepts, since it is only the immediate percept in its unique individuality or "thisness" —what theScholasticscalled itshaecceity—that stands beyond control and correction. Scientific concepts, on the other hand, are general in nature, and transient sensations do in another sense find correction within them. This notion of perception as abduction has received periodic revivals inartificial intelligenceandcognitive scienceresearch, most recently for instance with the work ofIrvin Rockonindirect perception.[46][47]
Around the beginning of the 20th century, William James (1842–1910) coined the term "radical empiricism"to describe an offshoot of his form of pragmatism, which he argued could be dealt with separately from his pragmatism—though in fact the two concepts are intertwined in James's published lectures. James maintained that the empirically observed" directly apprehended universe needs... no extraneous trans-empirical connective support ",[48]by which he meant to rule out the perception that there can be anyvalue addedby seekingsupernaturalexplanations fornaturalphenomena.James' "radical empiricism" is thusnotradical in the context of the term "empiricism", but is instead fairly consistent with the modern use of the term "empirical".His method of argument in arriving at this view, however, still readily encounters debate within philosophy even today.
John Dewey(1859–1952) modified James' pragmatism to form a theory known asinstrumentalism.The role of sense experience in Dewey's theory is crucial, in that he saw experience as unified totality of things through which everything else is interrelated. Dewey's basic thought, in accordance with empiricism, was thatrealityis determined by past experience. Therefore, humans adapt their past experiences of things to perform experiments upon and test the pragmatic values of such experience. The value of such experience is measured experientially and scientifically, and the results of such tests generate ideas that serve as instruments for future experimentation,[49]in physical sciences as in ethics.[50]Thus, ideas in Dewey's system retain their empiricist flavour in that they are only knowna posteriori.
See also
[edit]- Abstract empiricism– 1959 book by C. Wright Mills
- Empirical idealism– Philosophy that only minds and ideas are real
- Empirical realism– 1781 book by Immanuel Kant
- Empirical relationship– Mathematical relationship or correlation based solely on observation rather than theory
- Empirical research– Research using empirical evidence
- Empirical sociology
- Feminist empiricism– Perspective within feminist research
- Ground truth– Information provided by direct observation
- History of scientific method
- Inquiry– Any process that has the aim of augmenting knowledge, resolving doubt, or solving a problem
- Kantian empiricism– American philosopher (1912–1989)
- Natural philosophy– Philosophical study of nature
- Naturalism– Belief that only natural laws and forces operate in the universe
- Objectivity– Basic distinction in philosophy
- Positivism– Empiricist philosophical theory
- Psychological nativism– View in psychology about the brain
- Quasi-empirical method
- Sensualism– Epistemological position
- Transcendental Empiricism– French philosopher (1925–1995)
Endnotes
[edit]- ^Psillos, Stathis; Curd, Martin (2010).The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science(1. publ. in paperback ed.). London: Routledge. pp. 129–38.ISBN978-0415546133.
- ^"Francis Bacon and the Four Idols of the Mind".
- ^Baird, Forrest E.; Walter Kaufmann (2008).From Plato to Derrida.Upper Saddle River, New Jersey: Pearson Prentice Hall.ISBN978-0-13-158591-1.[page needed]
- ^abcdHume, D. "An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding", in Enquiries Concerning the Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals, 2nd edition, L.A. Selby-Bigge (ed.),Oxford University Press,Oxford, UK, 1902 [1748].[page needed]
- ^Scheibe, Erhard. (2001).Between rationalism and empiricism: selected papers in the philosophy of physics.Springer.ISBN0-387-98520-4.OCLC45888831.
- ^Shelley, M. (2006). Empiricism. In F. English (Ed.), Encyclopedia of educational leadership and administration. (pp. 338–39). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, Inc.
- ^"Definition of EMPIRIC".merriam-webster.20 January 2024.
- ^Markie, P. (2004), "Rationalism vs. Empiricism" in Edward D. Zalta (ed.),Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,Eprint.
- ^Loeb, Luis E. (1981).From Descartes to Hume: Continental Metaphysics and the Development of Modern Philosophy.Ithaca: Cornell University Press.ISBN0801412897.[page needed]
- ^Engfer, Hans-Jürgen (1996),Empirismus versus Rationalismus? Kritik eines philosophiegeschichtlichen Schemas,Paderborn: Schöningh.[page needed]
- ^Buckle, Stephen (1999), "British Sceptical Realism. A Fresh Look at the British Tradition",European Journal of Philosophy,7, pp. 1–2.
- ^Peter Anstey, "ESP is bestArchived2013-12-31 at theWayback Machine",Early Modern Experimental Philosophy,2010.
- ^DPS Bhawuk (2011), Spirituality and Indian Psychology (Editor: Anthony Marsella), Springer,ISBN978-1-4419-8109-7,page 172
- ^Eliott Deutsche (2000), in Philosophy of Religion: Indian Philosophy Vol 4 (Editor: Roy Perrett), Routledge,ISBN978-0815336112,pages 245-248
- ^John A. Grimes, A Concise Dictionary of Indian Philosophy: Sanskrit Terms Defined in English, State University of New York Press,ISBN978-0791430675,page 238
- ^"Greek Medicine: Alexander the Great".greekmedicine.net.
- ^Sini, Carlo (2004), "Empirismo", in Gianni Vattimo et al. (eds.),Enciclopedia Garzanti della Filosofia.
- ^Bardzell, Jeffrey (June 11, 2014).Speculative Grammar and Stoic Language Theory in Medieval Allegorical Narrative: From Prudentius to Alan of Lille.Routledge. pp. 18–19.
- ^Diels-Kranz 4.11 translated byLong, A. A.; Sedley, D. N. (1987).The Hellenistic Philosophers: Vol. 1.Cambridge, Ma: Cambridge. p. 238.
- ^abSajjad H. Rizvi (2006),Avicenna/Ibn Sina (c. 980–1037),Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- ^abG. A. Russell (1994),The 'Arabick' Interest of the Natural Philosophers in Seventeenth-Century England,pp. 224–62,Brill Publishers,ISBN90-04-09459-8
- ^Dr. Abu Shadi Al-Roubi (1982), "Ibn Al-Nafis as a philosopher",Symposium on Ibn al-Nafis,Second International Conference on Islamic Medicine: Islamic Medical Organization, Kuwait (cf.Ibn al-Nafis As a PhilosopherArchivedFebruary 6, 2008, at theWayback Machine,Encyclopedia of Islamic World)
- ^"Seeing the Body: The Divergence of Ancient Chineseand Western Medical Illustration", Camillia Matuk, Journal of Biocommunication, Vol. 32, No. 1, 2006,[1]Archived2017-01-24 at theWayback Machine
- ^abcBoenke, Michaela, "Bernardino Telesio", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL =https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/telesio/.
- ^Markie, Peter (August 19, 2004)."Rationalism vs. Empiricism".Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.RetrievedAugust 27,2024.
- ^Vanzo, Alberto (January 2013)."KANT ON EMPIRICISM AND RATIONALISM".jstor.University of Illinois Press.RetrievedAugust 27,2024.
- ^Thornton, Stephen (1987) "Berkeley's Theory of Reality" inThe Journal of the Limerick Philosophical Society,UL.ieArchived2011-09-18 at theWayback Machine
- ^Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1969), "George Berkeley", vol. 1, p. 297.
- ^abcdMacmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1969), "Empiricism", vol. 2, p. 503.
- ^Hume."Of Probability".Enquiries Concerning the Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals.
- ^Hume."Of the Idea of a Necessary Connexion".Enquiries Concerning the Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals.
- ^Morick, H. (1980), Challenges to Empiricism, Hackett Publishing, Indianapolis, IN.
- ^Marconi, Diego (2004), "Fenomenismo" ', inGianni Vattimoand Gaetano Chiurazzi (eds.),L'Enciclopedia Garzanti di Filosofia,3rd edition, Garzanti, Milan, Italy.
- ^Mill, J.S., "An Examination of Sir William Rowan Hamilton's Philosophy", in A.J. Ayer and Ramond Winch (eds.), British Empirical Philosophers, Simon and Schuster, New York, NY, 1968.[page needed]
- ^Wilson, Fred (2005), "John Stuart Mill", in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ^abcMacmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1969), "Phenomenalism", vol. 6, p. 131.
- ^Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1969), "Axiomatic Method", vol. 5, pp. 188–89, 191ff.
- ^Bolender, John (1998), "Factual Phenomenalism: A Supervenience Theory" ', Sorites, no. 9, pp. 16–31.
- ^Berlin, Isaiah (2004), The Refutation of Phenomenalism, Isaiah Berlin Virtual Library.
- ^Chisholm, Roderick M. (September 9, 1948). "The Problem of Empiricism".The Journal of Philosophy.45(19): 512–17.doi:10.2307/2019108.JSTOR2019108.
- ^Achinstein, Peter,andBarker, Stephen F.(1969), The Legacy of Logical Positivism: Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, MD.[page needed]
- ^Barone, Francesco (1986), Il neopositivismo logico, Laterza, Roma Bari.[page needed]
- ^Rescher, Nicholas(1985), The Heritage of Logical Positivism, University Press of America, Lanham, MD.
- ^Burch, Robert (2017). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.).The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy(Fall 2017 ed.). Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
- ^Ward, Teddy (n.d.), "Empiricism",EprintArchived2012-07-14 atarchive.today.
- ^Rock, Irvin (1983), The Logic of Perception, MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.[page needed]
- ^Rock, Irvin, (1997) Indirect Perception, MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.[page needed]
- ^James, William (1911), The Meaning of Truth.
- ^Dewey, John (1906), Studies in Logical Theory.[page needed]
- ^Weber, Eric Thomas (2011). "What Experimentalism Means in Ethics".The Journal of Speculative Philosophy.25:98–115.doi:10.1353/jsp.2011.0000.S2CID144868257.
References
[edit]- Achinstein, Peter, and Barker, Stephen F. (1969),The Legacy of Logical Positivism: Studies in the Philosophy of Science,Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, MD.
- Aristotle,"On the Soul"(De Anima),W. S. Hett(trans.), pp. 1–203 inAristotle, Volume 8,Loeb Classical Library,William Heinemann,London, UK, 1936.
- Aristotle,Posterior Analytics.
- Barone, Francesco (1986),Il neopositivismo logico,Laterza, Roma Bari
- Berlin, Isaiah (2004),The Refutation of Phenomenalism,Isaiah Berlin Virtual Library.
- Bolender, John (1998), "Factual Phenomenalism: A Supervenience Theory" ',Sorites,no. 9, pp. 16–31.
- Chisolm, R. (1948), "The Problem of Empiricism",Journal of Philosophy45, 512–17.
- Dewey, John (1906),Studies in Logical Theory.
- Encyclopædia Britannica,"Empiricism", vol. 4, p. 480.
- Hume, D.,A Treatise of Human Nature,L.A. Selby-Bigge (ed.), Oxford University Press, London, UK, 1975.
- Hume, David. "An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding", inEnquiries Concerning the Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals,2nd edition, L.A. Selby-Bigge (ed.), Oxford University Press, Oxford, UK, 1902.Gutenberg press full-text
- James, William (1911),The Meaning of Truth.
- Keeton, Morris T.(1962), "Empiricism", pp. 89–90 in Dagobert D. Runes (ed.),Dictionary of Philosophy,Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ.
- Leftow, Brian (ed., 2006),Aquinas: Summa Theologiae, Questions on God,pp. viiet seq.
- Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy(1969), "Development of Aristotle's Thought", vol. 1, pp. 153ff.
- Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy(1969), "George Berkeley", vol. 1, p. 297.
- Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy(1969), "Empiricism", vol. 2, p. 503.
- Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy(1969), "Mathematics, Foundations of", vol. 5, pp. 188–89.
- Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy(1969), "Axiomatic Method", vol. 5, pp. 192ff.
- Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy(1969), "Epistemological Discussion", subsections on "A Priori Knowledge" and "Axioms".
- Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy(1969), "Phenomenalism", vol. 6, p. 131.
- Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy(1969), "Thomas Aquinas", subsection on "Theory of Knowledge", vol. 8, pp. 106–07.
- Marconi, Diego (2004), "Fenomenismo" ', inGianni Vattimoand Gaetano Chiurazzi (eds.),L'Enciclopedia Garzanti di Filosofia,3rd edition, Garzanti, Milan, Italy.
- Markie, P. (2004), "Rationalism vs. Empiricism" in Edward D. Zalta (ed.),Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,Eprint.
- Maxwell, Nicholas(1998),The Comprehensibility of the Universe: A New Conception of Science,Oxford University Press, Oxford.
- Mill, J.S., "An Examination of Sir William Rowan Hamilton's Philosophy", in A.J. Ayer and Ramond Winch (eds.),British Empirical Philosophers,Simon and Schuster, New York, NY, 1968.
- Morick, H. (1980),Challenges to Empiricism,Hackett Publishing,Indianapolis, IN.
- Peirce, C.S.,"Lectures on Pragmatism", Cambridge, Massachusetts, March 26 – May 17, 1903. Reprinted in part,Collected Papers,CP 5.14–212. Published in full with editor's introduction and commentary, Patricia Ann Turisi (ed.),Pragmatism as a Principle and Method of Right Thinking: The 1903 Harvard "Lectures on Pragmatism",State University of New York Press, Albany, NY, 1997. Reprinted, pp. 133–241, Peirce Edition Project (eds.),The Essential Peirce, Selected Philosophical Writings, Volume 2 (1893–1913),Indiana University Press,Bloomington, IN, 1998.
- Rescher, Nicholas (1985),The Heritage of Logical Positivism,University Press of America, Lanham, MD.
- Rock, Irvin(1983),The Logic of Perception,MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
- Rock, Irvin, (1997)Indirect Perception,MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts.
- Runes, D.D.(ed., 1962),Dictionary of Philosophy,Littlefield, Adams, and Company, Totowa, NJ.
- Sini, Carlo (2004), "Empirismo", in Gianni Vattimo et al. (eds.),Enciclopedia Garzanti della Filosofia.
- Solomon, Robert C., and Higgins, Kathleen M. (1996),A Short History of Philosophy,pp. 68–74.
- Sorabji, Richard (1972),Aristotle on Memory.
- Thornton, Stephen (1987),Berkeley's Theory of Reality,EprintArchived2011-09-18 at theWayback Machine
- Vanzo, Alberto (2014), "From Empirics to Empiricists",Intellectual History Review,2014, Eprint availablehereandhere.
- Ward, Teddy (n.d.), "Empiricism",Eprint.
- Wilson, Fred (2005), "John Stuart Mill", in Edward N. Zalta (ed.),Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,Eprint.