Jump to content

Gerhard Ritter

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Gerhard Georg Bernhard Ritter(6 April 1888, inBad Sooden-Allendorf– 1 July 1967, inFreiburg) was a Germanhistorianwho served as a professor of history at theUniversity of Freiburgfrom 1925 to 1956. He studied under ProfessorHermann Oncken.ALutheran,he first became well known for his 1925 biography ofMartin Lutherand hagiographic portrayal ofPrussia.[1]A member of theGerman People's Partyduring theWeimar Republic,he was a lifelongmonarchistand remained sympathetic to the political system of the defunctGerman Empire.

A critic of bothdemocracyandtotalitarianism,he supportedauthoritarianrule and German supremacy in Europe. His vision of history was narrowed to German interests, had little sympathy for foreign nations, and was full of disdain forCatholicism.[2]Eventually, his conflict with theNazi regimegot him arrested by it in 1944.

After World War II, Ritter worked to restore German nationalism by attempting to separate it from Nazi ideology and favored pursuit of German national interests, rather than reconciliation with the victims of German aggression. At the end of his career, he argued against theories of the German historianFritz Fischer.Ritter became an honorary member of theAmerican Historical Associationin 1959.

Early life[edit]

Ritter was born inBad Sooden-Allendorf(now in the federal state ofHesse,in Central Germany). His father was aLutheranclergyman. The young Ritter was educated at agymnasiuminGütersloh.

University studies[edit]

His studies were continued at the Universities ofMunich,HeidelbergandLeipzig.Ritter began serving as a teacher in 1912. While studying at Heidelberg, he was a research assistant to the national-liberal historianHermann Oncken,who was a major influence on Ritter.[3]Professor Oncken opposed the Nazis and was forced to resign in 1935.

Ritter's first book was published in 1913:Die preußischen Konservativen und Bismarcks deutsche Politik(The Prussian Conservatives and Bismarck's German Policy). It was hisPhDdissertation completed in 1911 under the supervision of Oncken.[4]Ritter examined the dispute betweenOtto von Bismarckand conservativePrussian Junkersfrom 1858 to 1876. The Junkers felt that Bismarck's policy was a menace to their traditional privileges.[4]A source of special conflict between Bismarck and the Junkers was their opposition to Bismarck's compromises with the southern German states, which were seen as a threat to the traditional powers that they enjoyed.[4]The theme of the extent of one's allegiance to those who hold power would be a recurring subject in Ritter's works.[4]

First World War[edit]

Ritter fought as aninfantrymanin theFirst World War.Ritter was strongly committed to a German victory. He criticised the ideology ofPan-German Leagueas chauvinistic nationalism, but he found it difficult to come to terms with the German defeat.[5]

He regarded the German defeat of 1918 as a great disaster.[4]Ritter believed that the monarchy had been the best form of government for Germany and that theWeimar Republicwas a grave mistake since Germany did not have a tradition ofrepublicanism.[4]Ritter subscribed to the 19th-century view of history as a form of political education for the elite, and contemporary politics were always a pressing concern for him.[4]

Marriage and family[edit]

In 1919, he married Gertrud Reichardt with whom he had three children.

Weimar Republic[edit]

Ritter worked as a professor atHeidelberg University(1918–1923),Hamburg University(1923–1925) andFreiburg University(1925–1956). During his time at Heidelberg, he began an official history of the university from theMiddle Agesto the present, but only one volume was ever published.[5]

Biography of Luther[edit]

In 1925, Ritter published a sympatheticbiographyofMartin Lutherthat made his reputation as a historian. Ritter treated his subject as an excellent example of the "eternal German".[4]Ritter argued against the view of Luther as an opportunist, which was promoted byErnst TroeltschandMax Weber,and instead contended that Luther was a man of faith, who possessed the ability to expose what Ritter regarded as grave flaws in theCatholic Church.[4]Ritter argued that Luther had inspired his followers to have the self-confidence to improve the world.[6]

Ritter's Luther biography was written in large part under the impact of the defeat of 1918 and so Ritter went to great lengths to defend what he regarded as the unique German spirit against what Ritter saw as the corrupt materialist spiritual outlook of the West.[7]Throughout his life,Lutheranismwas a major influence on Ritter's writings.[8]

In particular, Ritter agreed with Luther's argument that the moral values of Christianity were relevant to only the individual, not the state.[6]Citing Luther, Ritter argued that the state had to hold power and that as part of the messy business of politics, it could be guided only by the Christian values of its leaders.[6]Taking up of the ideas of Rudolf Kjellén and Friedrich Patzel, Ritter argued that the state should be regarded as a living entity, which, to live successfully, required economic and territorial growth.[6]Using that argument, Ritter contended thatFrederick the Great's invasion ofSilesiain 1740 was a necessary act to allow the Prussian state to live regardless of international laws against aggression.[6]

Stein biography[edit]

During the last years of the Weimar Republic, Ritter changed his focus from the medieval period to the early modern period to the modern period and from cultural history to biographies of political figures.[9]In 1931, Ritter wrote the biography of thePrussianstatesmenKarl vom Stein.Ritter's two-volume work portrayed Stein as the total opposite ofBismarck.[6]Ritter argued that Bismarck was the ultimate power politician and that Stein was the ultimate anti-power politician.[6]Ritter argued that Stein's success as a politician was limited by his moralism but contended that despite his lack of political sense, he was nonetheless successful because of his strong moral character.[6]

Views on eve of Nazi takeover[edit]

On 11 February 1933, in a letter to a friend, Ritter described his intentions:

I am planning to write two books. One will be entitled 'What is Liberalism?', and will be the attempt to pave the way for the founding of a large national party of the center, a party which we need today more than ever before. The book will contribute to the drafting of a new liberal national program, which will offer political orientation based on historical reflection.... The second book is to...shed light on the great crises in the political and intellectual history of Germany, and will thus explain the present state of mind of the German people. This second book will serve two purposes. It will develop a new concept of the history of our nation... and it will help deepen the notion of the idea of German nationality and national consciousness after a time which this idea has in public use become unbearably trivial. New tasks are crowding in upon us. In our era the historian acquires a distinctive national function, an educational function. Certainly, for the time being no one wants to listen to him, because everyone is still running after noisy political agitators. But I am confident that a time will come when everyone will be thoroughly fed up with the din of national phrase-making and will long for a pure drink instead of the inebriating potion administered by the Nazis. The historian has to prepare positions for the reserves... ".[10]

Already, at mid-day on January 30, 1933, in a fateful step, German PresidentPaul von Hindenburghad confirmed the leader of theNazi Partyas the newGerman chancellor,who would lead, for a time, a minority government.[11]

Nazi regime[edit]

Initial support[edit]

Initially, Ritter supported the Nazi regime despite severe doubts about the Nazis, particularly over the regime's persecution of the churches.[6]He reconciled himself to refraining from censure of the regime and its foreign policy. In 1940, he stated that "the sword is always more ready to the hand of continental statesman who stands in the midst of the fray of European power interests, and must always be armed to counter an attack before it is too late". He agreed withBenito Mussolinithat "might is the precondition of all freedom".[12]

Ritter publicly referred to the Nazi Reich as the "peaceful center of Europe" that would form a "bulwark against Bolshevism", and he praised the GermanAnschluss(union) withAustria.[13]Having supported well before 1933 the idea ofGreater Germany,Ritter at first defended the Nazi invasion as a realisation of the German hopes like most other people.[14]He went on record praising theAnschlussas the "boldest and most felicitous foreign policy feat of our new government".[15]

National conservative[edit]

Ritter was a staunch German nationalist and belonged to a political movement generally known to historians asnational conservatism.[6]He identified with the idea of anauthoritariangovernment in Germany that would make his country Europe's foremost power.[6]In an article published in early 1933, "Eternal Right and Interests of the State", he argued that the German people needed most was a government "in which a strong authoritarian leadership will gain voluntary popular allegiance because it is willing to respect eternal justice as well as freedom".[16]

The deep belief that Ritter had in aRechtsstaat(a state upheld by law) made him increasingly concerned at Nazi violations of legal codes.[16]In 1935, while remaining very cautious about his public comments on Nazism generally, he attempted to defend his mentor, Oncken, against attacks by Nazis. The party officials had objected to a paper by Oncken, which implied that the Nazi revolution was not the greatest revolution of all time.[17]

Frederick the Great biography[edit]

Ritter's 1936 short interpretive biography ofFrederick the Greathas been described by the American military historianPeter Paretas one of the finest military biographies ever written.[18]

The historianRussell Weigleycalled it "the best introduction to Frederick the Great and indeed to European warfare in his time".[19]James J. Sheehansays it is the best book in English on the famous king.[20]

Ritter's biography was designed as a challenge to Nazi ideology, which claimed a continuity between Frederick and Hitler. Dorpalen wrote: "The book was indeed a very courageous indictment of Hitler's irrationalism and recklessness, his ideological fanaticism and insatiable lust for power".[21]Dorpalen, nevertheless, criticised Ritter's historiography as apologetic of Prussian militarism, German past and figures like Frederick the Great and Bismarck[22]

Ritter's emphasis on Frederick's limited war aims and willingness to settle for less than he initially sought was seen at the time as a form of oblique criticism ofAdolf Hitler.[6]In addition, the emphasis that Ritter placed on the influence of theEnlightenmentand "orderly reason" on Fredrick were intended by Ritter to disprove Hitler's claim quietly of being Frederick's successor.[23]The inspiration behind the Fredrick biography was Ritter's personal reaction to theDay of Potsdam,22 March 1933, on which Hitler had laid claim to the Prussian traditions in a way that Ritter felt was not historically accurate.[24]

In March 1936, upon witnessing theremilitarization of the Rhineland,Ritter wrote in a letter to his mother that for his children "who had never seen German soldiers from close up, this is one of the greatest experiences ever.... Truly a great and magnificent experience. May God grant that it does not lead to some international catastrophe".[25]

Acts against regime[edit]

Ritter was a devout Lutheran and became a member of theConfessing Church,a group of dissenting Lutherans that resisted the Nazi-inspired and Nazi-imposed "Aryan Christianity" during the 1930s.[6]

In 1938, Ritter was the only faculty member at Freiburg to attend the funeral ofEdmund Husserl,who was considered the founder of the modern philosophical school ofphenomenology.Husserl had been on the faculty at the University of Freiburg until the Nazis in 1933 caused him to be dismissed because of hisJewishorigins. Husserl was then also prevented from publishing his works.

Ritter's presence at the funeral of Husserl has been widely interpreted ever since as an act of quiet courage and political protest against the Nazi regime.[26]After theKristallnachtpogrom, Ritter wrote in a letter to his mother, "What we have experienced over the last two weeks all over the country is the most shameful and most dreadful thing that has happened for a long time".[27]

In 1938, Ritter delivered a series of lectures inJenaattackingFriedrich Nietzsche.The lectures were intended by Ritter to be a form of indirect protest of the Nazi regime.[28]

1938 historicism debate with Meinecke[edit]

In 1938, Ritter became involved in a major debate withFriedrich Meineckeover "historism".[29]Meinecke argued in favor of the idea of celebrating the "valuable individual quality" of all the phenomenon of history, which was judged not by universal standards but only in regard to its own values.[29]Ritter attacked that position by arguing that without universal notions of values of good and evil and judging all historical phenomenon by its own standards was to abandon all ideas of morality applicable to all times and places.[29]

Freiburger Kreis[edit]

After the 1938Kristallnachtpogrom,Ritter became a founding member of theFreiburger Kreis,a discussion group whose focus wasneoliberalpolicy for the political economy. It was composed of anti-Nazi professors which included Adolf Lampe, Constantin von Dietze, Franz Böhm andWalter Eucken.[27]

Advisor to Goerdeler[edit]

Later, Ritter worked as an advisor to the German conservative politicianCarl Goerdeler.Together, they considered a future constitution after the overthrow of the Nazis. Both were involved in the secret plans to take down Hitler (see below).

In aDenkschriftsubmitted to Goerdeler in January 1943, Ritter wrote, "Hundreds of thousands of human beings have been systematically murdered solely because of their Jewish ancestry".[30]Although urging that theHolocaustshould be immediately ended, Ritter went on in the same memo to suggest that in a future post-Nazi government, themodern civil rights of Jewsshould be restricted.[30][31]

Book on Machiavelli and utopia[edit]

In 1940, Ritter publishedMachtstaat und Utopie(National Power and Utopia). In this book, Ritter argued thatdemocracywas a luxury that only militarily-secure states could afford.[6]Ritter argued that because Britain is an island, that provides a degree of security that allows democracy.[6]By contrast, Ritter argued that Germany, with its location inCentral Europeneeded an authoritarian government as the only way of maintaining security.[6]

Ritter also contrasted the utopianism of SirThomas Moreand the realism ofNiccolò Machiavelli.[9]Ritter declares that Germany had to follow the realism of Machiavelli because of the security requirements of its geographic position.[9]Ritter describes two sorts of values as generated by two different types of polities: one traditionally Anglo-Saxon and the other continental, as personified by the contrast of More and Machiavelli.[32]

Ritter praised Machiavelli as the ideal thinker who understood the "paradox of power", state power to be effective always involvin the use of or the threat of violence. Accordingly, society could not function without an armed police power to hold it together and a military against foreign threats.[32]Ritter criticised More for refusing to acknowledge the paradox of power. Instead, More seemed to think that morality could function in politics without the threat of and/or use of violence.[33]

Ritter presented traditional Anglo-Saxon thinking about power, which depend on an ineffective legalism, as inferior tocontinentalthinking, which is based on an understanding of the ultimate necessity of some form of violence.[34]The historian Gregory Weeks commented that it is hard to tell how much ofMachstaat und Utopiewas material that was inserted to allow the book to be passed by the censors and how much was the expression of Ritter's own beliefs. Weeks argued that if Ritter was no Nazi, he was certainly a German nationalist who wished to see Germany as the world's great power.[6]

Ritter appeared to disavow part of his original work of 1940 by the addition of a footnote to the third edition ofMachstaat und Utopiethat was published in 1943. Ritter praised More for his understanding of "the demoniacal forces of power" against which More had appealed to the strength ofChristian moralityand so More rightly did not reduce all politics to a "friend-foe" mentality.[35]The historian Klaus Schwabe observed that Ritter's disapproval of the term "friend-foe" was a not-so-veiled criticism ofCarl Schmitt,who had popularised the term a decade before and supported the Nazi regime. Thus, Ritter's criticism indirectly pointed at such Nazi "forces of power".[35]

Censored book on military[edit]

During World War II, Ritter became involved in work on a study of civilian-military relations in Germany from the 18th century to the 20th century.[36]The original intent behind this work was to offer a critique of the "total war"philosophy of General Ludendorff as a form of indirect protest against Nazi Germany.[36]Censorship prevented the book from being published during the war, and after 1945, Ritter revised his work to publish it as a four-volume study of German militarism.[36]

Assassination plot[edit]

Ritter was involved in the 20 July 1944Stauffenberg assassination plot[37]and was one of the few conspirators not liquidated by the Nazis. His friend and political associate,Carl Goerdeler,was slated to become the newchancellorunder a post-Nazi regime. If the coup had succeeded, the plotters planned to bargain with the Western Allies for Germany to keep territories in Eastern Europe, which were being invaded by theSoviet Union.Goerdeler was executed by the Nazis in 1945.

Ritter, who also belonged to theconservativeGerman opposition to the Nazis, was imprisoned in late 1944 for the rest of the war.[38]

Themes after World War II[edit]

Source of Nazi evils[edit]

Two major themes of Ritter's writings after 1945 were attempts to prove that the Bismarckian tradition in German life had nothing to do with national socialism and that it was democracy of the masses, rather than aristocratic conservatism, that had caused the Nazi movement.[9]After World War II, Ritter wrote the bookEuropa und die deutsche Frage(Europe and the German Question), which denied thatNazi Germanywas the inevitable product of German history but considered that it was rather in Ritter's view part of a general European drift towardstotalitarianismthat had been going on since theFrench Revolution;as such, Germans should not be singled out for criticism.[39]

In Ritter's opinion, the origins of National Socialism went back toJean-Jacques Rousseau's concept of thevolonté générale(general will) and theJacobins.[40]Ritter argued, "National Socialism is not an originally German growth, but the German form of a European phenomenon: the one-party orFührerstate ", which was the result of" modern industrial society with its uniform mass humanity ".[41]

Along the same lines, Ritter wrote that "not any event in German history, but the great French Revolution undermined the firm foundation of Europe's political traditions. It also coined the new concepts and slogans with whose help the modern state of theVolkand the Führer justifies its existence ".[42]Ritter argued that throughout the 19th century, there had been worrisome signs in Germany and the rest of Europe caused by the entry of masses into politics but that it was World War I that marked the decisive turning point.[43]

According to Ritter, World War I had caused a general collapse in moral values throughout the West, and it was that moral degeneration that led to the decline of Christianity, the rise of materialism, political corruption, the eclipse of civilization by barbarism and demagogic politics, which, in turn, led to National Socialism.[43]In Ritter's view, the problem with theWeimar Republicwas not that it lackeddemocracybut that it had too much democracy.[42]He argued that the democratic republic had left the German state open to being hijacked by the appeals of rabble-rousing extremists.[42]In Ritter's view, if his much belovedGerman Empirehad continued after 1918, there would have been no Nazi Germany.

Ritter argued thatdemocracywas the essential precondition of totalitarianism because it created the window of opportunity for a strongman to make himself the personification of the "popular will". That led Ritter to conclude that "the system of 'totalitarian' dictatorship as such is not a specifically German phenomenon" but that it was the natural result of when "the direct rule of the people derived from the 'revolt of the masses' is introduced".[42]Ritter argued that the precursors of Hitler were "neitherFrederick the Great,BismarcknorWilhelm II,but the demagogues andCaesarsof modern history fromDantontoLenintoMussolini".[44]

Rescue of German nationalism[edit]

Ritter saw his main task after 1945 of seeking to restore German nationalism against what he regarded as unjust slurs.[41]Ritter argued that Germans needed a positive view of their past but warned against the appeal of "false concepts of honor and national power".[41]He belonged to group of German historians that rejected reconciliation with victim of Nazi aggression but supported Germany its pursuing national interests.[45]

He railed against the fact that theAllies occupational authoritieshad confiscated German archives at the end of World War II and had begun to publish a critical edition of German foreign policy records without the participation of German historians. He used his official position as the first postwar head of the German Historical Association to demand the return of the records and held the opinion that their absence was hurting his own research projects the most.[46]

In his treatment of theGerman Resistance,Ritter drew a sharp line between those who worked with foreign powers to defeat Hitler and those likeCarl Friedrich Goerdelerwho sought to overthrow the Nazis but worked for Germany.[47]For Ritter, Goerdeler was a patriot, but the men and women of theRote Kapellespy network were traitors.[48]Ritter wrote that those involved in theRote Kapellewere not part of the "German Resistance, but stood in the service of the enemy abroad" and so fully deserved to be executed.[48]

Ecumenical progression[edit]

Besides defending German nationalism, Ritter became active in the ecumenical movement after 1945 and urged conservative Catholics and Protestants to come together in theChristian Democratic Union.He argued that based on his experience in Nazi Germany, Christians, regardless of their church, needed to work together against totalitarianism.[49]

During the war, as a result of his underground work, Ritter came to know a number of Catholic and Calvinist members of the German opposition, which caused Ritter to abandon his former prejudices against Calvinists and Catholics.[50]Ritter came to the conclusion that whatever differences divided Lutherans, Catholics and Calvinists, member of all three churches had more in common to unite them against the Nazis.[50]

Goerdeler biography[edit]

In 1954, Ritter published an acclaimed biography of Carl Goerdeler, a close friend, a conservative politician who was executed by theNazisin 1945. Goerdeler was a devout Lutheran and the son of a conservative Prussian politician. Ritter pushed for the translation of his Goerdeler biography into English to counter the publication of John W. Wheeler-Bennett's bookNemesis of Power,which in his view vilified the German resistance.[51]

German militarism[edit]

Ritter specialized in Germanpolitical,militaryandcultural history.Ritter always drew a sharp distinction between what he regarded as theMachtpolitik(power politics) of Bismarck in which military policy was subjected to carefully limited political goals and the endless expansionism that was motivated by militarism and bizarre racial theories of the Nazis.[9]

Ritter was well known for his assertions denying that there was a uniquely-aggressive German version ofmilitarism.[44]For Ritter, militarism was the "one-sided determination of political decisions on the basis of technical military considerations" and foreign expansionism, and it had nothing to do with values of a society.[52]

In a paper presented to the German Historical Convention in 1953, "The Problem of Militarism in Germany", Ritter argued traditional Prussian leaders such as Frederick the Great wereMachtpolitiker(power politicians), not militarists, since in Ritter's view, Frederick was opposed to "the ruthless sacrifice of all life to the purposes of war" and instead was interested in creating "a lasting order of laws and peace, to further general welfare, and to moderate the conflict of interests".[53]

Ritter maintained that militarism first appeared during theFrench Revolution,when the revolutionary French state, later to be followed byNapoleon I's regime, began the total mobilization of society to seek "the total destruction of the enemy".[53]Likewise, Ritter contended thatOtto von Bismarckwas aKabinettspolitker(Cabinet politician), not a militarist, and ensured that political considerations were always placed ahead of military considerations.[54]Ritter was to expand on these views in a four-volume studyStaatskunst und Kriegshandwerk(translated into English asThe Sword and the Scepter), published between 1954 and 1968, in which Ritter examined the development of militarism in Germany between 1890 and 1918.

In Volume 2 ofStaatskunst und Kriegshandwerk,Ritter commented that it was only after Bismarck's sacking in 1890 that militarism first appeared in Germany. Accordingly, a review of the first years of the 20th century was "not without a sense of psychological shock".[42]Ritter wrote that "the prewar Germany of my own youth, which has for an entire lifetime been illuminated in my memory by the radiant splendor of a sun that seemed to grow dark only after the outbreak of the war of 1914" was "in the evening of my life" darkened by "shadows that were much deeper than my generation-and certainly the generation of my academic teachers-was able to perceive at the time".[42]

For Ritter, it was the radicalizing experience of the First World War that had finally led to the triumph of militarism in Germany, especially after 1916, whenErich Ludendorffestablished his "silent dictatorship", which Ritter believed was a huge break with Prussian and German traditions.[54]It was the unhappy results of that war that finally led to the "proletarian nationalism" of the Nazis gaining a mass audience and to the "militarism of the National Socialist mass movement" coming to power.[55]Moreover, Ritter placed great emphasis on the "Hitler factor" as an explanation for Nazi Germany. In 1962, Ritter wrote that he found it "almost unbearable" that the "will of a single madman" had unnecessarily caused World War II.[43]

Critical views on German history[edit]

Though many regarded Ritter's work as an apologia for German nationalism and conservatism, Ritter was at times critical of aspects of the German past.[42]Though Ritter commented that many nations had bent their knees in submission to false values, "the Germans accepted all of that with special ardor when it was now preached to them by National Socialism, and their nationalism had in general displayed from its beginning a particularly intense, combative quality".[42]

At the first meeting of German historians in 1949, Ritter delivered a speech:

"We constantly run the risk not only of being condemned by the world as nationalists, but actually being misused as expert witnesses by all those circles and tendencies that, in their impatient andblind nationalism,have shut their ears to the teachings of the most recent past. Never was our political responsibility greater, not only to Germany, but also to Europe and the world. And yet never has our path been so dangerously narrow between Scylla and Charybdis as today ".[56]

In 1953, Ritter found a copy of the "Great Memorandum" relating to German military planning written by GeneralAlfred Graf von Schlieffenin 1905. The following year, Ritter published the "Great Memorandum" and his observations about theSchlieffen PlanasDer Schlieffen-Plan: Kritik Eines Mythos(The Schlieffen Plan: Critique of a Myth).

Role in Fischer Controversy[edit]

Break or continuity?[edit]

In his last years, Ritter emerged as the leading critic of the left-wing historianFritz Fischer,who claimed that there had been powerful lines of continuity between theGerman EmpireandNazi Germanyand that it was Germany that had caused World War I. During the ferocious "Fischer Controversy", which engulfed the West German historical profession in the 1960s, Ritter was the best known of Fischer's critics.[57]

Ritter fiercely rejected Fischer's arguments that Germany had been primarily responsible for the outbreak of war in 1914. The later volumes ofStaatskunst und Kriegshandwerkwere taken up with the goal of rebutting Fischer's arguments.[6]Ritter claimed that Germany had not started a war of aggression in 1914 but admitted that the situation of the German government had required a foreign policy, which contained the immediate risk of war.[6]Against Fischer's thesis, Ritter maintained that the ChancellorTheobald von Bethmann Hollweghad resisted the demands by GeneralLudendorfffor wide-ranging annexations as a war aim.[6]

Ritter's points against Fischer[edit]

As part of his critique of Fischer, Ritter contended that Germany's principal goal in 1914 was to maintain theAustria-Hungaryas a great power; thus, German foreign policy was largely defensive although Fischer claimed that it was mostly aggressive.[58]Ritter claimed that the significance that Fischer attached to the highly-bellicose advice about waging a "preventive war"in the Balkans offered in July 1914 to the Chief of Cabinet of the Austro-Hungarian Foreign Ministry, CountAlexander Hoyos,by the German journalist Viktor Naumann was unwarranted.[59]Ritter charged that Naumann was speaking as a private individual, but Fischer claimed that it was on behalf of the German government.[59]

Likewise, Ritter felt that Fischer had been dishonest in his portrayal of Austro-German relations in July 1914.[60]Ritter charged that Germany had not pressured a reluctant Austria-Hungary into attackingSerbia.[60]Ritter argued, ironically against Fischer, that the main impetus for war within Austria-Hungary came from domestic politics and was internally driven. There were divisions about the best course to pursue in Vienna and Budapest, but it was not German pressure that led Austria-Hungary to choose war as the best option.[61]

In Ritter's opinion, Germany may be criticized for its mistaken evaluation of the state of European power politics in July 1914.[61]According to Ritter, the German government had underrated the state of military readiness in Russia and France, falsely assumed that the British were unwilling to go to war over the violation of Belgianneutrality,overrated the sense of moral outrage caused by the assassination ofArchduke Franz Ferdinandon European opinion and above all overestimated the military power and political common sense of Austria-Hungary.[61]

Ritter felt that in retrospect, it was not necessary for Germany to maintain Austria-Hungary as a great power but claimed that at the time, most Germans regarded the Dual Monarchy as a "brother empire" and viewed the prospect of the Balkans being in the Russian sphere of influence as an unacceptable threat.[61]As opposed to Fischer's claim that Germany was deliberately setting off a war of aggression, Ritter argued that Germany's support for Austria-Hungary's retributive plan to invade Serbia was anad hocresponse to the crisis that was gripping Europe.[62]

Ritter accused Fischer of manufacturing the quote he attributed to German GeneralHelmuth von Moltke the Younger,Chief of the General Staff, during a meeting with Austro-Hungarian War Minister Field MarshalConrad von Hötzendorf,about the necessity of a "speedy attack" on Serbia.[62]Ritter claimed the importance that Fischer attached to the report of the German Army's quartermaster that the army was "ready" for war in 1914 was simply mistaken since the quartermaster always reported every year that the army was "ready" for war.[63]

Likewise, in reference to the order by Chancellor Bethmann Hollweg toSiegfried von Roedern,the State Secretary forAlsace-Lorraine,to end Francophobic remarks in the German-language press in Alsace, Ritter claimed that was proof of Germany's desire not to have a wider war in 1914. He accordingly claimed also that Fischer's contrary interpretation of Bethmann Hollweg's order was not supported by the facts.[64]

Contrary to Fischer's interpretation, Ritter maintained that Bethmann Hollweg's warnings to Vienna were sincerely meant to stop a war, rather than not window dressing intended to distract historical attention from Germany's responsibility for the war.[65]Ritter claimed that Fischer's interpretation of Bethmann Hollweg's meeting with British AmbassadorSir Edward Goschenwas mistaken since in Ritter's opinion, if Bethmann Hollweg was serious about securing British neutrality, it made no sense to express the German war aims to Goschen that Fischer attributed to him.[66]

Ritter strongly disagreed with Fischer's interpretation of the meeting of Moltke, Bethmann Hollweg and GeneralErich von Falkenhayn(the Prussian war minister) on 30 July 1914. Rather than a conscious decision to wage an aggressive war, as Fischer argued, Ritter's claim was that news of Russia's mobilisation led the German generals into persuading a reluctant Bethmann Hollweg to activate the Schlieffen Plan.[67]

Ritter was strongly critical of what he regarded as Fischer's "biased" view of Moltke's reaction to the outbreak of the war and argued that Moltke's opposition to the sudden last-minute suggestion ofWilhelm IIfor the German attack on France to be cancelled was for logistical concerns, rather than a desire to provoke a world war.[68]Finally, Ritter faults Fischer for his reliance on the memories of Austro-Hungarian leaders such as CountIstván Tiszaand CountOttokar Czernin,who sought to shift all of the responsibility for the war onto Germany.[68]

Ritter argued there were no lines of continuity between the German Empire and Nazi Germany and considered theSonderwegview ofGerman historyto be a myth. Ritter clearly denied Fischer's arguments that both world wars were "wars for hegemony" by Germany.[69]

In 1964, Ritter successfully lobbied the West German Foreign Ministry to cancel the travel funds that had been allocated for Fischer to visit the United States. In Ritter's opinion, giving Fischer a chance to express his "anti-German" views would be a "national tragedy" and so Fischer should not be allowed to have the government funds for his trip.[70]Writing in 1962, Ritter stated that he felt profound "sadness" over the prospect that Germans may not be as patriotic because of Fischer.[69]

Variety of outcomes[edit]

According toRichard J. Evans,the outcome of the Fischer Controversy and of Ritter's role in it "only succeeded in giving Fischer's massive, scholarly and extremely detailed book a national prominence it would probably not otherwise have achieved".[71]Evans notes that after his death, Ritter was usually cast as the "villain of this affair, as Fischer's views, at least in their more moderate forms, gained widespread acceptance among a younger generation of historians".[71]

A history book on Imperial Germany byHans-Ulrich Wehlerwas published in 1973 and held that as a result of Fischer's theories, "two opposing schools of thought" formed. The first agreed with Fischer. The second admitted that Fischer showed that much political talk in high circles that sounds quite warlike, but it held that Fischer failed to find the actual political decisions and military actions that he claimed.[72]

ProfessorWolfgang Mommsen(1930-2004) was a German historian of Britain and Germany on the 19th and the 20th centuries. His 1990 work credited Fischer's work in part for opening up the discussion. However, Mommsen characterised Fischer's "central notion of Germany's will to power" from 1911 to 1915 as being seriously flawed, as Fischer "has allowed himself to be carried away". The nature of his methodology worked to obscure his perspective, and Fischer's conclusions displayed a neglect of the historical context.[73]According to Mommsen, Fischer blamed Germany alone for aSocial Darwinismthat was then European.

Niall Fergusonis a British historian who served as a professor atOxford Universityand then atHarvard University.In his 1998 work on World War II,The Pity of War,Ferguson reviewed Fischer's claims about German objectives in a European war:

"Yet there is a fundamental flaw in Fischer's reasoning which too many historians have let pass. It is the assumption that Germany's aims as stated after the war had begun were the same as German aims beforehand." Ferguson then recited how a September 1914 program of German aims "is sometimes portrayed as if it were the first open statement of aims which had existed before the outbreak of war.... But the inescapable fact is that no evidence has ever been found by Fischer and his pupils that these objectives existedbeforeBritain's entry into the war.... All that Fischer can produce are the pre-war pipedreams of a few Pan-Germans and businessmen, none of which had any official status, as well as the occasional bellicose utterances of the Kaiser... ".[74]

Ferguson also criticised Fischer for seizing on the notion that right-wing officeholders in Germany used an aggressive foreign policy to gain domestic political advantage over the German left. Such misuse of foreign policy, Ferguson noted, "was hardly the invention of the German Right", which in effect repeated the charge made by Mommsen (see above) that Fischer neglected the historical context. In fact, conservative office holders in Germany were articulate and aware that a European war could lead to the ascendancy of the left whether the war was won or lost.[75]

Honored in America[edit]

In 1959, Ritter was elected an honorary member of theAmerican Historical Associationin recognition of what the Association described as his struggle withtotalitarianism.He was the fifth German historian to be so honored by the AHA, one of the last historians of the traditionalGerman idealistschool, which considered history as an art. He concerned himself with an imaginative identification with his subjects, focused on the great men of the times studied and was primarily concerned with political and military events.[76]

Bibliography[edit]

  • Die preußischen Konservativen und Bismarcks deutsche Politik, 1858 bis 1876,1913.
  • Luther: Gestalt und Symbol,1925.
  • Stein: eine politische Biographie,1931.
  • Friedrich der Große,1936.
  • Berthold Ritter zum Gedächtnis,1946.
  • Machstaat und Utopie: vom Streit um die Dämonie der Macht seit Machiavelli und Morus,1940, revised asDie Dämonie der Macht: Betrachtungen über Geschichte und Wesen des Machtproblems im politischen Denken der Neuzeit,1947.
  • Europa und die Deutsche Frage: Betrachtungen über die geschichtliche Eigenart des Deutschen Staatsdenkens,1948.
  • Die Neugestaltung Deutschlands und Europas im 16. Jahrhundert.,1950.
  • Karl Goerdeler und die Deutsche Widerstandsbewegung,1954.
  • Staatskunst und Kriegshandwerk: das Problem des "Militarismus" in Deutschland,4 volumes, 1954-1968.
    • translated asThe Sword and the Scepter: The Problem of Militarism in Germany(4 vol, University of Miami Press 1970);Vol 1,Vol 2,Vol 3andVol 4
  • Der Schlieffenplan: Kritik eines Mythos,1956.
  • "Eine neue Kriegsschuldthese?" pages 657-668 fromHistorische Zeitschrift,Volume 194, June 1962, translated into English as "Anti-Fischer: A New War-Guilt Thesis?" pages 135-142 fromThe Outbreak of World War One: Causes and Responsibilities,edited by Holger Herwig, Boston: Houghton Mifflin Co., 1997.

Notes[edit]

  1. ^The Quest for the Lost Nation: Writing History in Germany and Japan in the American Century (California World History Library) Sebastian Conrad page 128
  2. ^Paths of Continuity: Central European Historiography from the 1930s to the 1950s page 114 byHartmut Lehmann,James Van Horn Melton
  3. ^Schwabe, Klaus "Gerhard Ritter" pages 83-103 fromPaths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute, 1994 page 85.
  4. ^abcdefghiWeeks, Gregory (1999)."Ritter, Gerhard A."In Kelly Boyd, ed.,The Encyclopedia of Historians and Historical Writing.Chicago: Fitzroy Dearborn Publishers,p. 996.
  5. ^abSchwabe, Klaus (1994)."Gerhard Ritter."InHartmut Lehmann,ed.,Paths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute,p. 84.
  6. ^abcdefghijklmnopqrstWeeks, Gregory (1999)."Ritter, Gerhard A."In Kelly Boyd, ed.,The Encyclopedia of Historians and Historical Writing,Chicago: Fitzroy Dearborn Publishers,p. 997.
  7. ^Levine, Norman (1991). "Ritter, Gerhard" pages 304-306 fromGreat Historians of the Modern Ageedited by Lucan Boia, New York: Greenwood Press, 1991, page 305.
  8. ^Schwabe, Klaus (1994)."Gerhard Ritter."InHartmut Lehmann,ed.,Paths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute,p. 86.
  9. ^abcdeLevine, Norman "Ritter, Gerhard" pages 304-306 fromGreat Historians of the Modern Ageedited by Lucan Boia, New York: Greenwood Press, 1991, page 305.
  10. ^Schwabe, Klaus "Gerhard Ritter" pages 83-103 fromPaths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute, 1994 page 83.
  11. ^William L. Shirer,The Rise and Fall of the Third Reich(New York: Simon and Schuster 1960) at 187.
  12. ^Explaining Auschwitz and Hiroshima: Historians and the Second World War, 1945-1990 Richard J. B. Bosworth, Routledge, page 58
  13. ^The Quest for the Lost Nation: Writing History in Germany and Japan in the American Century, Sebastian Conrad, University of California Press, 2010, page 44
  14. ^Heidegger and Nazism, edited by Víctor Farías, Joseph Margolis, Tom Rockmore page 161
  15. ^Universities Under Dictatorship edited by John Connelly, Michael Grüttner page 97
  16. ^abSchwabe, Klaus "Gerhard Ritter" pages 83-103 fromPaths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute, 1994 page 88.
  17. ^Schwabe, Klaus "Gerhard Ritter" pages 83-103 fromPaths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute, 1994 page 91.
  18. ^Ritter, Gerhard(1974) [1936]. Peret, Peter (ed.).Frederick the Great: A Historical Profile.English translation. Berkeley: University of California Press.ISBN0-520-02775-2.
  19. ^Russell Frank Weigley (2004).The Age of Battles: The Quest for Decisive Warfare from Breitenfeld to Waterloo.Indiana U.P. p. 550.ISBN0253217075.
  20. ^James J. Sheehan (1993).German History, 1770-1866.Oxford U.P. p. 65n.ISBN9780198204329.
  21. ^Andreas Dorpalen, "Historiography as History: The Work of Gerhard Ritter."Journal of Modern History(1962) (March, 1962), p 9
  22. ^German History in Marxist Perspective: The East German Approach By Andreas Dorpalen, Foreword by Georg Iggers page 14, 1985
  23. ^Schwabe, Klaus "Gerhard Ritter" pages 83-103 fromPaths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute, 1994 page 95.
  24. ^Schwabe, Klaus "Gerhard Ritter" pages 83-103 fromPaths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute, 1994 pages 94-95.
  25. ^Stern, FritzDreams and Delusions: The Drama of German History,Yale: Yale University Press, 1999 page 176
  26. ^Friedländer, SaulNazi Germany and the Jews,New York: Harper Collins, 1997 page 54.
  27. ^abFriedländer, SaulNazi Germany and the Jews,New York: Harper Collins, 1997 page 297.
  28. ^Schwabe, Klaus "Gerhard Ritter" pages 83-103 fromPaths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute, 1994 pages 91-92.
  29. ^abcSchwabe, Klaus "Gerhard Ritter" pages 83-103 fromPaths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute, 1994 page 93.
  30. ^abIggers, Georg "Comment: German Historiography" pages 43-48 from Paths of Continuity edited byHartmut Lehmann& James Van Horn Melton, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994 page 44.
  31. ^Cf. Theodore S. Hamerow,On the Road to Wolf' Lair. German resistance to Hitler.(Harvard University 1997) at 182-187, 257-259, 326-329, 383-385, re Goerdeler.
  32. ^abSchwabe, Klaus "Gerhard Ritter" pages 83-103 fromPaths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute, 1994 page 99.
  33. ^Schwabe, Klaus "Gerhard Ritter" pages 83-103 fromPaths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute, 1994 pages 99-100.
  34. ^Schwabe, Klaus "Gerhard Ritter" pages 83-103 fromPaths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute, 1994 page 100.
  35. ^abSchwabe, Klaus "Gerhard Ritter" pages 83-103 fromPaths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute, 1994 page 101.
  36. ^abcSchwabe, Klaus "Gerhard Ritter" pages 83-103 fromPaths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute, 1994 page 97.
  37. ^Explaining Auschwitz and Hiroshima: Historians and the Second World War, 1945-1990 Richard J. B. Bosworth Routledge, page 58
  38. ^Weeks, Gregory "Ritter, Gerhard A." pages 996-998 fromThe Encyclopedia of Historians and Historical Writing,Volume 2 page 998.
  39. ^Kershaw, IanThe Nazi Dictatorship Problems and Perspectives of Interpretation,London: Arnold Press, 2000 page 7; Hamerow, Theodore S. "Guilt, Redemption and Writing German History" pages 53-72 fromThe American Historical Review,Volume 88, February 1983 pages 62-63
  40. ^Hamerow, Theodore S. "Guilt, Redemption and Writing German History" pages 53-72 fromThe American Historical Review,Volume 88, February 1983 page 62.
  41. ^abcIggers, GeorgThe German Conception of History,Middletown: Connecticut; Wesleyan University Press, 1968 page 258.
  42. ^abcdefghHamerow, Theodore S. "Guilt, Redemption and Writing German History" pages 53-72 fromThe American Historical Review,Volume 88, February 1983 page 63.
  43. ^abcKershaw, IanThe Nazi Dictatorship Problems and Perspectives of Interpretation,London: Arnold Press, 2000 page 7
  44. ^abIggers, GeorgThe German Conception of History,Middletown: Connecticut; Wesleyan University Press, 1968 page 254.
  45. ^The German Problem Transformed: Institutions, Politics, and Foreign Policy, 1945-1995 Thomas F. Banchoff University of Michigan Press, 1999 page 82
  46. ^Astrid M. Eckert, The Struggle for the Files. The Western Allies and the Return of German Archives after the Second World War (New York, Cambridge University Press, 2012), p. 293, 312-315, 381.ISBN978-0521880183
  47. ^Iggers, GeorgThe German Conception of History,Middletown: Connecticut; Wesleyan University Press, 1968 pages 258-259.
  48. ^abIggers, GeorgThe German Conception of History,Middletown: Connecticut; Wesleyan University Press, 1968 page 259.
  49. ^Schwabe, Klaus "Gerhard Ritter" pages 83-103 fromPaths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute, 1994 page 90.
  50. ^abSchwabe, Klaus "Gerhard Ritter" pages 83-103 fromPaths of ContinuityWashington, D.C.: German Historical Institute, 1994 page 89.
  51. ^Astrid M. Eckert, The Struggle for the Files. The Western Allies and the Return of German Archives after the Second World War (Cambridge University Press, Feb. 2012), p. 381.ISBN978-0521880183
  52. ^Iggers, GeorgThe German Conception of History,Middletown: Connecticut; Wesleyan University Press, 1968 page 255.
  53. ^abIggers, GeorgThe German Conception of History,Middletown: Connecticut; Wesleyan University Press, 1968 page 256.
  54. ^abIggers, GeorgThe German Conception of History,Middletown: Connecticut; Wesleyan University Press, 1968 pages 255-256.
  55. ^Iggers, GeorgThe German Conception of History,Middletown: Connecticut; Wesleyan University Press, 1968 pages 255-257.
  56. ^Hamerow, Theodore S. "Guilt, Redemption and Writing German History" pages 53-72 fromThe American Historical Review,Volume 88, February 1983 page 64.
  57. ^Ritter, Gerhard "Anti-Fischer" pages 135-142 fromThe Outbreak of World War Iedited by Holger Herwig, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997 page 135.
  58. ^Ritter, Gerhard "Anti-Fischer" pages 135-142 fromThe Outbreak of World War Iedited by Holger Herwig, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997 pages 135-136.
  59. ^abRitter, Gerhard "Anti-Fischer" pages 135-142 fromThe Outbreak of World War Iedited by Holger Herwig, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997 page 136.
  60. ^abRitter, Gerhard "Anti-Fischer" pages 135-142 fromThe Outbreak of World War Iedited by Holger Herwig, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997 pages 136-137.
  61. ^abcdRitter, Gerhard "Anti-Fischer" pages 135-142 fromThe Outbreak of World War Iedited by Holger Herwig, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997 page 137.
  62. ^abRitter, Gerhard "Anti-Fischer" pages 135-142 fromThe Outbreak of World War Iedited by Holger Herwig, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997 page 138.
  63. ^Ritter, Gerhard "Anti-Fischer" pages 135-142 fromThe Outbreak of World War Iedited by Holger Herwig, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997 pages 138-139.
  64. ^Ritter, Gerhard "Anti-Fischer" pages 135-142 fromThe Outbreak of World War Iedited by Holger Herwig, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997 page 139.
  65. ^Ritter, Gerhard "Anti-Fischer" pages 135-142 fromThe Outbreak of World War Iedited by Holger Herwig, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997 pages 139-140.
  66. ^Ritter, Gerhard "Anti-Fischer" pages 135-142 fromThe Outbreak of World War Iedited by Holger Herwig, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997 page 140.
  67. ^Ritter, Gerhard "Anti-Fischer" pages 135-142 fromThe Outbreak of World War Iedited by Holger Herwig, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997 pages 140-141.
  68. ^abRitter, Gerhard "Anti-Fischer" pages 135-142 fromThe Outbreak of World War Iedited by Holger Herwig, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997 page 141.
  69. ^abRitter, Gerhard "Anti-Fischer" pages 135-142 fromThe Outbreak of World War Iedited by Holger Herwig, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997 page 142.
  70. ^Herwig, Holger "Patriotic Self-Censorship in Germany" pages 153-159 fromThe Outbreak of World War Iedited by Holger Herwig, Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1997 page 158.
  71. ^abRichard Evans, 'Reviewed Work:Gerhard Ritter: Geschichtswissenschaft und Politik im 20. Jahrhundertby Christoph Cornelissen',The English Historical Review,Vol. 119, No. 482 (Jun., 2004), pp. 756-759.
  72. ^Wehler,The German Empire 1871-1918(1973; translation 1985) at 196.
  73. ^Wolfgang J. Mommsen,Der autoritäre Nationalstaat(Frankfurt am Main: Fischer Taschenbuch 1990), translated asImperial Germany 1867-1918. Politics, culture, and society in an authoritarian state(London: Arnold 1995) at 168-171.
  74. ^Niall Ferguson,The Pity of War. Explaining World War I(Harmondsworth: Allen Lane 1998; reprint 1999, Basic Books, New York) at 171-172.
  75. ^Ferguson,The Pity of War(1998, 1999) at 27-28; 28, 172.
  76. ^Levine, Norman "Ritter, Gerhard" pages 304-306 fromGreat Historians of the Modern Ageedited by Lucan Boia, New York: Greenwood Press, 1991, pages 305-306.

References[edit]

  • Dorpalen, Andreas "Gerhard Ritter" fromDeutsche Historiker,edited byHans-Ulrich Wehler,Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1973.
  • Dorpalen, Andreas "Historiography as History: The Work of Gerhard Ritter" pages 1–18 from theJournal of Modern History,Volume 34, 1962.in JSTOR
  • Hamerow, Theodore S. "Guilt, Redemption and Writing German History" pages 53–72 fromThe American Historical Review,Volume 88, February 1983.in JSTOR
  • Kershaw, IanThe Nazi Dictatorship Problems and Perspectives of Interpretation,London: Arnold Press, 2000,ISBN0-340-76928-9.
  • Jäckel, Eberhard"Gerhard Ritter, Historiker in seiner Zeit" pages 705–715 fromGeschichte in Wissenschaft und Unterricht,Volume 16, 1967.
  • Lehmann, Hartmut& Melton, James Van Horn (editors)Paths of Continuity: Central European Historiography from the 1930s to the 1950s,Washington, D.C.: German Historical Institute; Cambridge [England]; New York: Cambridge University Press, 1994ISBN0-521-45199-X.
  • Levine, Norman "Gerhard Ritter'sWeltanschauung"pages 209-227 fromReview of Politics,Volume 30, 1968.in JSTOR
  • Levine, Norman "Ritter, Gerhard" pages 304–306 fromGreat Historians of the Modern Ageedited by Lucian Boia, Westport, C.T.: Greenwood Press, 1991ISBN0-313-27328-6.
  • Maehl, William "Gerhard Ritter" fromHistorians of Modern Europeedited by Hans Schmitt, Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1971ISBN0-8071-0836-7.
  • Wolfgang Mommsen,Der autoritäre Nationalstaat(Frankfurt am Main: Fischer Taschenbuch 1990), translated asImperial Germany 1867–1918. Politics, culture, and society in an authoritarian state(London: Arnold 1995).
  • Moyn, Samuel, “The First Historian of Human Rights,”American Historical Review116:1 (2011), 58–79 [critical assessment of Ritter’s writings on the history of human rights in the 1940s and the field of human rights history].
  • Mruck, Armin: Review ofCarl Goerdeler und die deutsche Widerstandsbewegungpages 268–269 fromThe Journal of Modern History,Volume 30, Issue # 3, September 1958
  • Hans-Ulrich Wehler,Das Deutsche Kaiserreich(Gőttingen: Verlages Vandenhoeck und Ruprecht 1973), translated asThe German Empire 1871–1918(Providence: Berg 1985).
  • Ulrich Bayer:Gerhard Ritter (1888-1967).In: Johannes Ehmann (Hrsg.):Lebensbilder aus der evangelischen Kirche in Baden im 19. und 20. Jahrhundert.Band II:Kirchenpolitische Richtungen.Verlag Regionalkultur, Heidelberg u.a. 2010, S. 391415,ISBN978-3-89735-510-1.
  • Christoph Cornelißen:Gerhard Ritter. Geschichtswissenschaft und Politik im 20. Jahrhundert.Droste, Düsseldorf 2001,ISBN3-7700-1612-2.
  • Christoph Cornelißen (2003),"Ritter, Gerhard Georg Bernhard",Neue Deutsche Biographie(in German), vol. 21, Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, pp. 658–660;(full text online)
  • Konrad Fuchs (1994). "Gerhard Ritter". In Bautz, Traugott (ed.).Biographisch-Bibliographisches Kirchenlexikon (BBKL)(in German). Vol. 8. Herzberg: Bautz. cols. 412–414.ISBN3-88309-053-0.
  • Michael Matthiesen:Verlorene Identität. Der Historiker Arnold Berney und seine Freiburger Kollegen 1923–1938.Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht,Göttingen 2001ISBN3-525-36233-1(Ritter als Unterstützer des ab 1933 als Jude verfolgten Prof. Berney).
    • Zur Kritik an Gerhard Ritters politisch-philosophischer Position siehe: 1)Johan Huizinga,In de schaduwen van morgen, Kap. 14 (deutsch: Im Schatten von morgen, in: Ders.: Schriften zur Zeitkritik, Pantheon-Verlag 1948); 2) Julius Ebbinghaus, Philosophie der Freiheit, Bonn 1988, S. 11 ff.

Further reading[edit]

  • Boyd, Kelly. "Ritter, Gerhard A. 1888–1967 German political and cultural historian."Encyclopedia of Historians and Historical Writing(Routledge, 2019) pp. 996–998.