Jump to content

Noumenon

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Inphilosophy,anoumenon(/ˈnmənɒn/,/ˈn-/;fromGreek:νοούμενoν;pl.:noumena) is knowledge[1]posited as anobjectthat exists independently of humansense.[2]The termnoumenonis generally used in contrast with, or in relation to, the termphenomenon,which refers to anyobjectof the senses.Immanuel Kantfirst developed the notion of the noumenon as part of histranscendental idealism,suggesting that while we know the noumenal world to exist because humansensibilityis merely receptive, it is not itself sensible and must therefore remain otherwiseunknowableto us.[3]InKantian philosophy,the noumenon is often associated with the unknowable "thing-in-itself"(German:Ding an sich). However, the nature of the relationship between the two is not made explicit in Kant's work, and remains a subject of debate among Kant scholars as a result.

Etymology[edit]

TheGreekwordνοούμενoν,nooúmenon(pluralνοούμενα,nooúmena) is theneuter middle-passive present participleofνοεῖν,noeîn,'to think, to mean', which in turn originates from the wordνοῦς,noûs,anAtticcontractedform ofνόος,nóos,'perception, understanding, mind'.[a][4][5]A rough equivalent in English would be "that which is thought", or "the object of an act of thought".

Historical predecessors[edit]

The IndianVedāntaphilosophy (specificallyAdvaita), the roots of which go back to theVedic period,talks of theātman(self) in similar terms as the noumenon.

[6] Regarding the equivalent concepts inPlato,Ted Honderichwrites: "Platonic Ideas and Formsare noumena, and phenomena are things displaying themselves to the senses... This dichotomy is the most characteristic feature of Plato's dualism; that noumena and the noumenal world are objects of the highest knowledge, truths, and values is Plato's principal legacy to philosophy. "[7]

Kantian noumena[edit]

Overview[edit]

As expressed in Kant'sCritique of Pure Reason,human understandingis structured by "concepts of the understanding" or purecategories of understanding,found prior to experience in themindand which make outer experiences possible as counterpart to therationalfaculties of the mind.[8][9]

By Kant's account, when one employs a concept to describe or categorizenoumena(the objects of inquiry, investigation or analysis of the workings of the world), one is also employing a way of describing or categorizingphenomena(the observable manifestations of those objects of inquiry, investigation or analysis). Kant posited methods by which human understanding makes sense of and thus intuits phenomena that appear to the mind: the concepts of thetranscendental aesthetic,as well as that of thetranscendental analytic,transcendental logicandtranscendental deduction.[10][11][12]Taken together, Kant's "categories of understanding" are the principles of the human mind which necessarily are brought to bear in attempting to understand the world in which weexist(that is, to understand, or attempt to understand, "things in themselves" ). In each instance the word "transcendental" refers to the process that the human mind must exercise to understand or grasp the form of, and order among, phenomena. Kant asserts that to "transcend" a direct observation or experience is to use reason and classifications to strive to correlate with the phenomena that are observed.[citation needed]Humans can make sense out of phenomena in these various ways, but in doing so can never know the "things-in-themselves", the actual objects and dynamics of the natural world in their noumenal dimension - this being the negative, correlate to phenomena and that which escapes the limits of human understanding. By Kant's Critique, our minds may attempt to correlate in useful ways, perhaps even closely accurate ways, with the structure and order of the various aspects of the universe, but cannot know these "things-in-themselves" (noumena) directly. Rather, we must infer the extent to which the human rational faculties can reach the object of "things-in-themselves" by our observations of the manifestations of those things that can be perceived via the physical senses, that is, of phenomena, and by ordering these perceptions in the mind help infer the validity of our perceptions to the rational categories used to understand them in a rational system. This rational system (transcendental analytic), being the categories of the understanding as free from empirical contingency.[13][14]

According to Kant, objects of which we are cognizant via the physical senses are merely representations ofunknown somethings—what Kant refers to as thetranscendental object—as interpreted through thea prioriorcategories of the understanding.Theseunknown somethingsare manifested within the noumenon—although we can never know how or why as our perceptions of theseunknown somethingsvia our physical senses are bound by the limitations of thecategories of the understandingand we are therefore never able to fully know the "thing-in-itself".[15]

Noumenon and the thing-in-itself[edit]

Many accounts of Kant's philosophy treat "noumenon" and "thing-in-itself" as synonymous, and there is textual evidence for this relationship.[16]However,Stephen Palmquistholds that "noumenon" and "thing-in-itself" are onlylooselysynonymous, inasmuch as they represent the same concept viewed from two different perspectives,[17][18]and other scholars also argue that they are not identical.[19]Schopenhauer criticised Kantfor changing the meaning of "noumenon". However, this opinion is far from unanimous.[20]Kant's writings show points of difference between noumena and things-in-themselves. For instance, he regards things-in-themselves as existing:

...though we cannot know these objects as things in themselves, we must yet be in a position at least to think them as things in themselves; otherwise we should be landed in the absurd conclusion that there can be appearance without anything that appears.[21]

He is much more doubtful about noumena:

But in that case a noumenon is not for our understanding a special [kind of] object, namely, an intelligible object; the [sort of] understanding to which it might belong is itself a problem. For we cannot in the least represent to ourselves the possibility of an understanding which should know its object, not discursively through categories, but intuitively in a non-sensible intuition.[22]

A crucial difference between the noumenon and the thing-in-itself is that to call something a noumenon is to claim a kind of knowledge, whereas Kant insisted that the thing-in-itself is unknowable. Interpreters have debated whether the latter claim makes sense: it seems to imply that we know at least one thing about the thing-in-itself (i.e., that it is unknowable). But Stephen Palmquist explains that this is part of Kant's definition of the term, to the extent that anyone who claims to have found a way of making the thing-in-itself knowable must be adopting a non-Kantian position.[23]

Positive and negative noumena[edit]

Kant also makes a distinction betweenpositiveandnegativenoumena:[24][25]

If by 'noumenon' we mean a thing so far as it is not an object of our sensible intuition, and so abstract from our mode of intuiting it, this is a noumenon in thenegativesense of the term.[26]

But if we understand by it an object of a non-sensible intuition, we thereby presuppose a special mode of intuition, namely, the intellectual, which is not that which we possess, and of which we cannot comprehend even the possibility. This would be 'noumenon' in thepositivesense of the term.[26]

The positive noumena, if they existed, would be immaterial entities that can only be apprehended by a special, non-sensory faculty: "intellectual intuition" (nicht sinnlicheAnschauung).[26]Kant doubts that we have such a faculty, because for him intellectual intuition would mean that thinking of an entity, and its being represented, would be the same. He argues that humans have no way to apprehend positive noumena:

Since, however, such a type of intuition, intellectual intuition, forms no part whatsoever of our faculty of knowledge, it follows that the employment of the categories can never extend further than to the objects of experience. Doubtless, indeed, there are intelligible entities corresponding to the sensible entities; there may also be intelligible entities to which our sensible faculty of intuition has no relation whatsoever; but our concepts of understanding, being mere forms of thought for our sensible intuition, could not in the least apply to them. That, therefore, which we entitle 'noumenon' must be understood as being such only in a negative sense.[27]

The noumenon as a limiting concept[edit]

Even if noumena are unknowable, they are still needed as alimiting concept,[28]Kant tells us. Without them, there would be only phenomena, and since potentially we have complete knowledge of our phenomena, we would in a sense know everything. In his own words:

Further, the concept of a noumenon is necessary, to prevent sensible intuition from being extended to things in themselves, and thus to limit the objective validity of sensible knowledge.[29]

What our understanding acquires through this concept of a noumenon, is a negative extension; that is to say, understanding is not limited through sensibility; on the contrary, it itself limits sensibility by applying the term noumena to things in themselves (things not regarded as appearances). But in so doing it at the same time sets limits to itself, recognising that it cannot know these noumena through any of the categories, and that it must therefore think them only under the title of an unknown something.[30]

Furthermore, for Kant, the existence of a noumenal world limits reason to what he perceives to be its proper bounds, making many questions of traditional metaphysics, such as the existence of God, the soul, and free will unanswerable by reason. Kant derives this from hisdefinition of knowledgeas "the determination of given representations to an object".[31]As there are no appearances of these entities in the phenomenal, Kant is able to make the claim that they cannot be known to a mind that works upon "such knowledge that has to do only with appearances".[32]These questions are ultimately the "proper object of faith, but not of reason".[33]

The dual-object and dual-aspect interpretations[edit]

Kantian scholars have long debated two contrasting interpretations of the thing-in-itself. One is thedual objectview, according to which the thing-in-itself is an entity distinct from the phenomena to which it gives rise. The other is thedual aspectview, according to which the thing-in-itself and the thing-as-it-appears are two "sides" of the same thing. This view is supported by the textual fact that "Most occurrences of the phrase 'things-in-themselves' are shorthand for the phrase, 'things considered in themselves' (Dinge an sich selbst betrachtet)."[34] Although we cannotseethings apart from the way we do in fact perceive them via the physical senses, we canthinkthem apart from our mode of sensibility (physical perception); thus making the thing-in-itself a kind of noumenon or object of thought.

Criticisms of Kant's noumenon[edit]

Pre-Kantian critique[edit]

Though the termnoumenondid not come into common usage until Kant, the idea that undergirds it, that matter has an absolute existence which causes it to emanate certain phenomena, had historically been subjected to criticism.George Berkeley,who pre-dated Kant, asserted that matter, independent of an observant mind, is metaphysically impossible. Qualities associated with matter, such as shape, color, smell, texture, weight, temperature, and sound are all dependent on minds, which allow only for relative perception, not absolute perception. The complete absence of such minds (and more importantly anomnipotent mind) would render those same qualities unobservable and even unimaginable. Berkeley called this philosophyimmaterialism.Essentially there could be no such thing as matter without a mind.[35]

Schopenhauer's critique[edit]

Schopenhauerclaimed thatKantused the wordnoumenonincorrectly. He explained in his "Critique of the Kantian philosophy",which first appeared as an appendix toThe World as Will and Representation:

The difference between abstract and intuitive cognition, which Kant entirely overlooks, was the very one that ancient philosophers indicated as φαινόμενα [phainomena] and νοούμενα [nooumena]; the opposition and incommensurability between these terms proved very productive in the philosophemes of theEleatics,inPlato's doctrine ofIdeas,in the dialectic of theMegarics,and later in thescholastics,in the conflict betweennominalismandrealism.This latter conflict was the late development of a seed already present in the opposed tendencies of Plato andAristotle.But Kant, who completely and irresponsibly neglected the issue for which the terms φαινομένα and νοούμενα were already in use, then took possession of the terms as if they were stray and ownerless, and used them as designations ofthings in themselvesand their appearances.[36]

The noumenon's original meaning of "that which is thought" is not compatible with the "thing-in-itself,"the latter being Kant's term for things as they exist apart from their existence as images in the mind of an observer.[citation needed]In a footnote to this passage, Schopenhauer provides the following passage from theOutlines of Pyrrhonism(Bk. I, ch. 13) ofSextus Empiricusto demonstrate the original distinction between phenomenon and noumenon according to ancient philosophers: νοούμενα φαινομένοις ἀντετίθη Ἀναξαγόρας ('Anaxagoras opposed what is thought to what appears.')

See also[edit]

Notes[edit]

  1. ^Ontology

References[edit]

  1. ^"Formal Epistemology".The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2021.
  2. ^"Noumenon | Definition of Noumenon by Webster's Online Dictionary".Archived fromthe originalon 28 September 2011.Retrieved10 September2015.1. intellectual conception of a thing as it is in itself, not as it is known through perception; 2. The of-itself-unknown and unknowable rational object, or thing-in-itself, which is distinguished from the phenomenon through which it is apprehended by the physical senses, and by which it is interpreted and understood; – so used in the philosophy of Kant and his followers.
  3. ^"noumenon | philosophy".Encyclopedia Britannica.Retrieved4 September2017.
  4. ^νοεῖν,νοῦς,νόος.Liddell, Henry George;Scott, Robert;A Greek–English Lexiconat thePerseus Project.
  5. ^Harper, Douglas."noumenon".Online Etymology Dictionary.
  6. ^https:// degruyter /document/doi/10.1515/9783110226249.2.194/pdf
  7. ^Honderich, Ted,ed. (31 August 1995).The Oxford Companion to Philosophy.Oxford University Press.p.657.ISBN0198661320.Retrieved28 October2014.
  8. ^Hanna, Robert (2009).Completing the Picture of Kant's Metaphysics of Judgment.Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  9. ^Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on Kant's metaphysics.
  10. ^The Encyclopedia of Philosophy(Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Critique of Pure Reason: Theme and Preliminaries", p. 308ff.
  11. ^The Encyclopedia of Philosophy(Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Transcendental Aesthetic", p. 310ff.
  12. ^The Encyclopedia of Philosophy(Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Pure Concepts of the Understanding", p. 311ff.
  13. ^See, e.g.,The Encyclopedia of Philosophy(Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Critique of Pure Reason: Theme and Preliminaries", p. 308ff.
  14. ^See also, e.g.,The Encyclopedia of Philosophy(Macmillan, 1967, 1996) Volume 4, "Kant, Immanuel", section on "Pure Concepts of the Understanding", p. 311ff.
  15. ^Kant 1999,p. 27, A256/B312.
  16. ^Immanuel Kant (1781)Critique of Pure Reason,for example in A254/B310, p. 362 (Guyer and Wood), "The concept of anoumenon,i.e., of a thing that is not to be thought of as an object of the senses but rather as a thing-in-itself [...] "; But note that the terms are not used interchangeably throughout. The first reference tothing-in-itselfcomes many pages (A30) before the first reference tonoumenon(A250). For a secondary or tertiary source, see:"Noumenon"in theEncyclopædia Britannica
  17. ^"Noumenon: the name given to a thing when it is viewed as a transcendent object. The term 'negative noumenon' refers only to the recognition of something which is not an object of sensible intuition, while 'positive noumenon' refers to the (quite mistaken) attempt to know such a thing as an empirical object. These two terms are sometimes used loosely as synonyms for 'transcendental object' and 'thing-in-itself', respectively. (Cf. phenomenon.)" –Glossary of Kant's Technical Terms
  18. ^Thing-in-itself: an object considered transcendentally apart from all the conditions under which a subject can gain knowledge of it via the physical senses. Hence the thing-in-itself is, by definition, unknowable via the physical senses. Sometimes used loosely as a synonym of noumenon. (Cf. appearance.) "–Glossary of Kant's Technical Terms.Palmquist defends his definitions of these terms in his article, "Six Perspectives on the Object in Kant's Theory of Knowledge",Dialectica40:2 (1986), pp.121–151; revised and reprinted as Chapter VI in Palmquist's book,Kant's System of Perspectives(Lanham: University Press of America, 1993).
  19. ^Oizerman, T. I.,"Kant's Doctrine of the" Things in Themselves "and Noumena", Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 41, No. 3, Mar., 1981, 333–350; Karin de Boer, "Kant's Multi-Layered Conception of Things in Themselves, Transcendental Objects, and Monads", Kant-Studien 105/2, 2014, 221-260.
  20. ^"Other interpreters have introduced an almost unending stream of varying suggestions as to how these terms ought to be used. A handful of examples will be sufficient to make this point clear, without any claim to represent an exhaustive overview. Perhaps the most commonly accepted view is expressed by Paulsen, who equates 'thing-in-itself' and 'noumenon', equates 'appearance' and 'phenomenon', distinguishes 'positive noumenon' and 'negative noumenon', and treats 'negative noumenon' as equivalent to 'transcendental object' [pp. 4:148-50, 154-5, 192]. Al-Azm and Wolff also seem satisfied to equate 'phenomenon' and 'appearance', though they both carefully distinguish 'thing-in-itself' from 'negative noumenon' and 'positive noumenon' [A4:520; W21:165, 313–5; s.a. W9:162]. Gotterbarn similarly equates the former pair, as well as 'thing-in-itself' and 'positive noumenon', but distinguishes between 'transcendental object', 'negative noumenon' and 'thing-in-itself' [G11: 201]. By contrast, Bird and George both distinguish between 'appearance' and 'phenomenon', but not between 'thing-in-itself' and 'noumenon' [B20:18,19, 53–7; G7:513-4n]; and Bird sometimes blurs the distinction between 'thing-in-itself' and 'transcendental object' as well.[2] Gram equates 'thing-in-itself' not with 'noumenon', but with 'phenomenon' [G13:1,5-6]! Allison cites different official meanings for each term, yet he tends to equate 'thing-in-itself' at times with 'negative noumenon' and at times with 'transcendental-object', usually ignoring the role of the 'positive noumenon' [A7:94; A10:58,69]. And Buchdahl responds to the fact that the thing-in-itself seems to be connected with each of the other object-terms by regarding it as 'Kant's umbrella term'.[3]"Stephen Palmquist on Kant's object terms
  21. ^Kant 1999,Bxxvi-xxvii.
  22. ^Kant 1999,p. 273, A256, B312.
  23. ^"The Radical Unknowability of Kant's 'Thing in Itself'", Cogito 3:2 (March 1985), pp.101–115; revised and reprinted as Appendix V in Stephen Palmquist,Kant's System of Perspectives(Lanham: University Press of America, 1993).
  24. ^Mattey, G. J.
  25. ^Lecture notes by G. J. MatteyArchived2010-06-12 at theWayback Machine
  26. ^abcKant 1999,p. 267 (NKS), A250/B307.
  27. ^Kant 1999,p. 270 (NKS), B309.
  28. ^Allison, H (2006)."Transcendental Realism, Empirical Realism, and Transcendental Idealism".Kantian Review.11:1–28.doi:10.1017/S1369415400002223.S2CID171078596.
  29. ^Kant 1999,A253/B310.
  30. ^Kant 1999,p. 273, A256/B312.
  31. ^Kant 1999,p. 156, B/137.
  32. ^Kant 1999,p. 24, B/xx..
  33. ^Rohmann, Chris. "Kant"A World of Ideas: A Dictionary of Important Theories, Concepts, Beliefs, and Thnkers.Ballantine Books, 1999.
  34. ^Mattey, GJ."Lecture Notes on the Critique of Pure Reason".
  35. ^Anon., "Caird's Philosophy of Kant",Saturday Review of Politics, Literature, Science and Art,vol 44, Nov 3, 1877,pp. 559-60.
  36. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur (2014).The World as Will and Representation, Volume 1.Translated by Norman, Judith; Welchman, Alistair; Janaway, Christopher. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 506.ISBN9780521871846.

Bibliography[edit]

External links[edit]