Jump to content

Arthur Schopenhauer

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected fromSchopenhauer)

Arthur Schopenhauer
Schopenhauer in 1855
Born(1788-02-22)22 February 1788
Died21 September 1860(1860-09-21)(aged 72)
NationalityGerman
Education
Relatives
Era19th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
School
InstitutionsUniversity of Berlin
Main interests
Metaphysics,aesthetics,ethics,morality,psychology
Notable ideas
Signature

Arthur Schopenhauer(/ˈʃpənhaʊər/SHOH-pən-how-ər,[9]German:[ˈaʁtuːɐ̯ˈʃoːpn̩haʊɐ];22 February 1788 – 21 September 1860) was a German philosopher. He is known for his 1818 workThe World as Will and Representation(expanded in 1844), which characterizes thephenomenalworld as the manifestation of a blind and irrationalnoumenalwill.[10][11][12]Building on thetranscendental idealismofImmanuel Kant(1724–1804), Schopenhauer developed anatheisticmetaphysical and ethical system that rejected the contemporaneous ideas ofGerman idealism.[7][8]

Schopenhauer was among the first thinkers inWestern philosophyto share and affirm significant tenets ofIndian philosophy,such asasceticism,denial of theself,and the notion of theworld-as-appearance.[13]His work has been described as an exemplary manifestation ofphilosophical pessimism.[14]Though his work failed to garner substantial attention during his lifetime, he had a posthumous impact across various disciplines, including philosophy, literature, and science. His writing onaesthetics,morality,andpsychologyhave influenced many thinkers and artists.

Life[edit]

Early life[edit]

Schopenhauer's birthplace house, ul. Św. Ducha

Arthur Schopenhauer was born on 22 February 1788, inGdańsk(then part of thePolish–Lithuanian Commonwealth;later in theKingdom of PrussiaDanzig) on Św. Ducha 47 (in Prussia Heiliggeistgasse), the son ofJohanna Schopenhauer(née Trosiener; 1766–1838) and Heinrich Floris Schopenhauer (1747–1805),[15]both descendants of wealthy Germanpatricianfamilies. While they came from a Protestant background, neither of them was very religious;[16]: 79 [17]both supported theFrench Revolution,[16]: 13 wererepublicans,cosmopolitansandAnglophiles.[16]: 9 When Gdańsk became part ofPrussiain 1793, Heinrich moved toHamburg—a free city with a republican constitution. His firm continued trading in Danzig where most of their extended families remained.Adele,Arthur's only sibling, was born on 12 July 1797.

In 1797, Arthur was sent toLe Havreto live with the family of his father's business associate, Grégoire de Blésimaire. He seemed to enjoy his two-year stay there, learning to speak French and fostering a life-long friendship with Jean Anthime Grégoire de Blésimaire.[16]: 18 As early as 1799, Arthur started playing the flute.[16]: 30 

In 1803, he accompanied his parents on a European tour ofHolland,Britain, France,Switzerland,AustriaandPrussia.Viewed as primarily a pleasure tour, Heinrich used the opportunity to visit some of his business associates abroad.

Heinrich presented Arthur with a choice: he could either stay at home to begin preparations for university or travel with them to further his merchant education. Arthur chose to travel with them. He deeply regretted his choice later because the merchant training was very tedious. He spent twelve weeks of the tour attending school inWimbledon,where he was confused by strict and intellectualAnglicanswho he'd described as shallow. He continued to sharply criticize Anglican religiosity later in life despite his general Anglophilia.[16]: 56 He was also under pressure from his father, who became very critical of his educational results.

In 1805, Heinrich drowned in a canal near their home in Hamburg. Although it was possible that his death was accidental, his wife and son believed that it was suicide. He was prone toanxietyanddepression,each becoming more pronounced later in his life.[18]Heinrich had become so fussy, even his wife started to doubt his mental health.[16]: 43 "There was, in the father's life, some dark and vague source of fear which later made him hurl himself to his death from the attic of his house in Hamburg."[16]: 88 

Arthur showed similar moodiness during his youth and often acknowledged that he inherited it from his father. There were other instances of serious mental health problems on his father's side of the family.[16]: 4 Despite his hardship, Schopenhauer liked his father and later referred to him in a positive light.[16]: 90 Heinrich Schopenhauer left the family with a significant inheritance that was split in three among Johanna and the children. Arthur Schopenhauer was entitled to control of his part when he reached the age of majority. He invested it conservatively in government bonds and earned annual interest that was more than double the salary of a university professor.[16]: 136 After quitting his merchant apprenticeship, with some encouragement from his mother, he dedicated himself to studies at theErnestine Gymnasium, Gotha,inSaxe-Gotha-Altenburg.While there, he also enjoyed social life among the local nobility, spending large amounts of money, which deeply concerned his frugal mother.[16]: 128 He left the Gymnasium after writing a satirical poem about one of the schoolmasters. Although Arthur claimed that he left voluntarily, his mother's letter indicates that he may have been expelled.[16]: 129 

Schopenhauer in his youth

Arthur spent two years as a merchant in honor of his dead father. During this time, he had doubts about being able to start a new life as a scholar.[16]: 120 Most of his prior education was as a practical merchant and he had trouble learning Latin; a prerequisite for an academic career.[16]: 117 

His mother moved away, with her daughter Adele, toWeimar—then the centre ofGerman literature—to enjoy social life among writers and artists. Arthur and his mother did not part on good terms. In one letter, she wrote: "You are unbearable and burdensome, and very hard to live with; all your good qualities are overshadowed by your conceit, and made useless to the world simply because you cannot restrain your propensity to pick holes in other people."[19]His mother, Johanna, was generally described as vivacious and sociable.[16]: 9 She died 24 years later. Some of Arthur's negative opinions about women may be rooted in his troubled relationship with his mother.[20]

Arthur moved to Hamburg to live with his friend Jean Anthime, who was also studying to become a merchant.

Education[edit]

He moved to Weimar but did not live with his mother, who even tried to discourage him from coming by explaining that they would not get along very well.[16]: 131 Their relationship deteriorated even further due to their temperamental differences. He accused his mother of being financially irresponsible, flirtatious and seeking to remarry, which he considered an insult to his father's memory.[16]: 116,131 His mother, while professing her love to him, criticized him sharply for being moody, tactless, and argumentative, and urged him to improve his behavior so that he would not alienate people.[16]: 129 Arthur concentrated on his studies, which were now going very well, and he also enjoyed the usual social life such as balls, parties and theater. By that time Johanna's famous salon was well established among local intellectuals and dignitaries, the most celebrated of them beingGoethe.Arthur attended her parties, usually when he knew that Goethe would be there—although the famous writer and statesman seemed not even to notice the young and unknown student. It is possible that Goethe kept a distance because Johanna warned him about her son's depressive and combative nature, or because Goethe was then on bad terms with Arthur's language instructor and roommate,Franz Passow.[16]: 134 Schopenhauer was also captivated by the beautifulKaroline Jagemann,mistress ofKarl August, Grand Duke of Saxe-Weimar-Eisenach,and he wrote to her his only known love poem.[16]: 135 Despite his later celebration of asceticism and negative views of sexuality, Schopenhauer occasionally had sexual affairs—usually with women of lower social status, such as servants, actresses, and sometimes even paid prostitutes.[16]: 21 In a letter to his friend Anthime he claims that such affairs continued even in his mature age and admits that he had two out-of-wedlock daughters (born in 1819 and 1836), both of whom died in infancy.[16]: 25 In their youthful correspondence Arthur and Anthime were somewhat boastful and competitive about their sexual exploits—but Schopenhauer seemed aware that women usually did not find him very charming or physically attractive, and his desires often remained unfulfilled.[16]: 22 

He left Weimar to become a student at theUniversity of Göttingenin 1809. There are no written reasons about why Schopenhauer chose that university instead of the then more famousUniversity of Jena,but Göttingen was known as more modern and scientifically oriented, with less attention given to theology.[16]: 140 Law or medicine were usual choices for young men of Schopenhauer's status who also needed career and income; he chose medicine due to hisscientific interests.Among his notable professors wereBernhard Friedrich Thibaut,Arnold Hermann Ludwig Heeren,Johann Friedrich Blumenbach,Friedrich Stromeyer,Heinrich Adolf Schrader,Johann Tobias MayerandKonrad Johann Martin Langenbeck.[16]: 141–144 He studiedmetaphysics,psychologyandlogicunderGottlob Ernst Schulze,the author ofAenesidemus,who made a strong impression and advised him to concentrate onPlatoandImmanuel Kant.[16]: 144 He decided to switch from medicine to philosophy around 1810–11 and he left Göttingen, which did not have a strong philosophy program: besides Schulze, the only other philosophy professor wasFriedrich Bouterwek,whom Schopenhauer disliked.[16]: 150 He did not regret his medicinal and scientific studies; he claimed that they were necessary for a philosopher, and even in Berlin he attended more lectures in sciences than in philosophy.[16]: 170 During his days at Göttingen, he spent considerable time studying, but also continued his flute playing and social life. His friends includedFriedrich Gotthilf Osann,Karl Witte,Christian Charles Josias von Bunsen,andWilliam Backhouse Astor Sr.[16]: 151 

He arrived at the newly foundedUniversity of Berlinfor the winter semester of 1811–12. At the same time, his mother had just begun her literary career; she published her first book in 1810, a biography of her friendKarl Ludwig Fernow,which was a critical success. Arthur attended lectures by the prominentpost-KantianphilosopherJohann Gottlieb Fichte,but quickly found many points of disagreement with hisWissenschaftslehre;he also found Fichte's lectures tedious and hard to understand.[16]: 159 He later mentioned Fichte only in critical, negative terms[16]: 159 —seeing his philosophy as a lower-quality version of Kant's and considering it useful only because Fichte's poor arguments unintentionally highlighted some failings of Kantianism.[16]: 165–169 He also attended the lectures of the famous Protestant theologianFriedrich Schleiermacher,whom he also quickly came to dislike.[16]: 174 His notes and comments on Schleiermacher's lectures show that Schopenhauer was becoming verycritical of religionand moving towardsatheism.[16]: 175 He learned by self-directed reading; besides Plato, Kant and Fichte he also read the works ofSchelling,Fries,Jacobi,Bacon,Locke,and much current scientific literature.[16]: 170 He attended philological courses byAugust BöckhandFriedrich August Wolfand continued his naturalistic interests with courses byMartin Heinrich Klaproth,Paul Erman,Johann Elert Bode,Ernst Gottfried Fischer,Johann Horkel,Friedrich Christian RosenthalandHinrich Lichtenstein(Lichtenstein was also a friend whom he met at one of his mother's parties in Weimar).[16]: 171–174 

Early work[edit]

Schopenhauer left Berlin in a rush in 1813, fearing that the city could be attacked and that he could be pressed into military service as Prussia had just joined thewar against France.[16]: 179 He returned to Weimar but left after less than a month, disgusted by the fact that his mother was now living with her supposed lover,Georg Friedrich Konrad Ludwig Müller von Gerstenbergk[de] (1778–1838), a civil servant twelve years younger than her; he considered the relationship an act of infidelity to his father's memory.[16]: 188 He settled for a while inRudolstadt,hoping that no army would pass through the small town. He spent his time in solitude, hiking in the mountains and theThuringian Forestand writing his dissertation,On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason.He completed his dissertation at about the same time as the French army was defeated at theBattle of Leipzig.He became irritated by the arrival of soldiers in the town and accepted his mother's invitation to visit her in Weimar. She tried to convince him that her relationship with Gerstenbergk was platonic and that she had no intention of remarrying.[16]: 230 But Schopenhauer remained suspicious and often came in conflict with Gerstenbergk because he considered him untalented, pretentious, andnationalistic.[16]: 231 His mother had just published her second book,Reminiscences of a Journey in the Years 1803, 1804, and 1805,a description of their family tour of Europe, which quickly became a hit. She found his dissertation incomprehensible and said it was unlikely that anyone would ever buy a copy. In a fit of temper Arthur told her that people would read his work long after the "rubbish" she wrote was totally forgotten.[21][22]In fact, although they considered her novels of dubious quality, theBrockhaus publishing firmheld her in high esteem because they consistently sold well. Hans Brockhaus (1888–1965) later claimed that his predecessors "saw nothing in this manuscript, but wanted to please one of our best-selling authors by publishing her son's work. We published more and more of her son Arthur's work and today nobody remembers Johanna, but her son's works are in steady demand and contribute to Brockhaus' reputation."[23]He kept large portraits of the pair in his office inLeipzigfor the edification of his new editors.[23]

Also contrary to his mother's prediction, Schopenhauer's dissertation made an impression on Goethe, to whom he sent it as a gift.[16]: 241 Although it is doubtful that Goethe agreed with Schopenhauer's philosophical positions, he was impressed by his intellect and extensive scientific education.[16]: 243 Their subsequent meetings and correspondence were a great honor to a young philosopher, who was finally acknowledged by his intellectual hero. They mostly discussed Goethe's newly published (and somewhat lukewarmly received) work oncolor theory.Schopenhauer soon started writing his own treatise on the subject,On Vision and Colors,which in many points differed from his teacher's. Although they remained polite towards each other, their growing theoretical disagreements—and especially Schopenhauer's extreme self-confidence and tactless criticisms—soon made Goethe become distant again and after 1816 their correspondence became less frequent.[16]: 247–265 Schopenhauer later admitted that he was greatly hurt by this rejection, but he continued to praise Goethe, and considered his color theory a great introduction to his own.[16]: 252,256,265 

Another important experience during his stay in Weimar was his acquaintance with Friedrich Majer[24]—ahistorian of religion,orientalistand disciple ofHerder—who introduced him toEastern philosophy[25][16]: 266 (see alsoIndology). Schopenhauer was immediately impressed by theUpanishads(he called them "the production of the highest human wisdom", and believed that they contained superhuman concepts) and theBuddha,[25]and put them on a par with Plato and Kant.[16]: 268,272 He continued his studies by reading theBhagavad Gita,an amateurish German journalAsiatisches MagazinandAsiatick Researchesbythe Asiatic Society.[16]: 267,272 Schopenhauer held a profound respect forIndian philosophy;[26]although he lovedHindu texts,he never revered a Buddhist text but regardedBuddhismas the most distinguished religion.[27][16]: 272 His studies on Hindu and Buddhist texts were constrained by the lack of adequate literature,[28]and the latter were mostly restricted toTheravada Buddhism.He also claimed that he formulated most of his ideas independently,[25]and only later realized the similarities with Buddhism.[16]: 274–276 

Schopenhauer read the Latin translation and praised the Upanishads in his main work,The World as Will and Representation(1819), as well as in hisParerga and Paralipomena(1851), and commented

In the whole world there is no study so beneficial and so elevating as that of the Upanishads. It has been the solace of my life, it will be the solace of my death.[29]

Schopenhauer in 1815. Portrait by Ludwig Sigismund Ruhl.

As the relationship with his mother fell to a new low, in May 1814 he left Weimar and moved toDresden.[16]: 265 He continued his philosophical studies, enjoyed the cultural life, socialized with intellectuals and engaged in sexual affairs.[16]: 284 His friends in Dresden wereJohann Gottlob von Quandt,Friedrich Laun,Karl Christian Friedrich Krauseand Ludwig Sigismund Ruhl, a young painter who made a romanticized portrait of him in which he improved some of Schopenhauer's unattractive physical features.[16]: 278,283 His criticisms of local artists occasionally caused public quarrels when he ran into them in public.[16]: 282 Schopenhauer's main occupation during his stay in Dresden was his seminal philosophical work,The World as Will and Representation,which he started writing in 1814 and finished in 1818.[30]He was recommended to the publisherFriedrich Arnold Brockhausby Baron Ferdinand von Biedenfeld, an acquaintance of his mother.[16]: 285 Although Brockhaus accepted his manuscript, Schopenhauer made a poor impression because of his quarrelsome and fussy attitude, as well as very poor sales of the book after it was published in December 1818.[16]: 285–289 

In September 1818, while waiting for his book to be published and conveniently escaping an affair with a maid that caused an unwanted pregnancy,[16]: 342 Schopenhauer left Dresden for a year-long vacation in Italy.[16]: 346 He visitedVenice,Bologna,Florence,NaplesandMilan,travelling alone or accompanied by mostly English tourists he met.[16]: 350 He spent the winter months inRome,where he accidentally met his acquaintanceKarl Witteand engaged in numerous quarrels with German tourists in theCaffè Greco,among themJohann Friedrich Böhmer,who also mentioned his insulting remarks and unpleasant character.[16]: 348–349 He enjoyed art, architecture, and ancient ruins, attended plays and operas, and continued his philosophical contemplation and love affairs.[16]: 346–350 One of his affairs supposedly became serious, and for a while he contemplated marriage to a rich Italian noblewoman—but, despite his mentioning this several times, no details are known and it may have been Schopenhauer exaggerating.[31][16]: 345 He corresponded regularly with his sister Adele and became close to her as her relationship with Johanna and Gerstenbergk also deteriorated.[16]: 344 She informed him about their financial troubles as the banking house of A. L. Muhl in Danzig—in which her mother invested their whole savings and Arthur a third of his—was near bankruptcy.[16]: 351 Arthur offered to share his assets, but his mother refused and became further enraged by his insulting comments.[16]: 352 The women managed to receive only thirty percent of their savings while Arthur, using his business knowledge, took a suspicious and aggressive stance towards the banker and eventually received his part in full.[16]: 354–356 The affair additionally worsened the relationships among all three members of the Schopenhauer family.[16]: 352,354 

He shortened his stay in Italy because of the trouble with Muhl and returned to Dresden.[16]: 356 Disturbed by the financial risk and the lack of responses to his book he decided to take an academic position since it provided him with both income and an opportunity to promote his views.[16]: 358 He contacted his friends at universities in Heidelberg, Göttingen and Berlin and foundBerlinmost attractive.[16]: 358–362 He scheduled his lectures to coincide with those of the famous philosopherG. W. F. Hegel,whom Schopenhauer described as a "clumsy charlatan".[32]He was especially appalled by Hegel's supposedly poor knowledge of natural sciences and tried to engage him in a quarrel about it already at his test lecture in March 1820.[16]: 363 Hegel was also facing political suspicions at the time, when many progressive professors werefired,while Schopenhauer carefully mentioned in his application that he had no interest in politics.[16]: 362 Despite their differences and the arrogant request to schedule lectures at the same time as his own, Hegel still voted to accept Schopenhauer to the university.[16]: 365 Only five students turned up to Schopenhauer's lectures, and he dropped out ofacademia.A late essay, "On University Philosophy", expressed his resentment towards the work conducted in academies.

Later life[edit]

Sculpture of Arthur Schopenhauer byGiennadij Jerszow

After his trying in academia, he continued to travel extensively, visitingLeipzig,Nuremberg,Stuttgart,Schaffhausen,Vevey,Milan and spending eight months in Florence.[16]: 411 Before he left for his three-year travel, Schopenhauer had an incident with his Berlin neighbor, 47-year-old seamstress Caroline Louise Marquet. The details of the August 1821 incident are unknown. He claimed that he had just pushed her from his entrance after she had rudely refused to leave, and that she had purposely fallen to the ground so that she could sue him. She claimed that he had attacked her so violently that she had become paralyzed on her right side and unable to work. She immediately sued him, and the process lasted until May 1827, when a court found Schopenhauer guilty and forced him to pay her an annual pension until her death in 1842.[16]: 408–411 

Schopenhauer enjoyed Italy, where he studied art and socialized with Italian and English nobles.[16]: 411–414 It was his last visit to the country. He left forMunichand stayed there for a year, mostly recuperating from various health issues, some of them possibly caused by venereal diseases (the treatment his doctor used suggestssyphilis).[16]: 415 He contacted publishers, offering to translate Hume into German and Kant into English, but his proposals were declined.[16]: 417,422 Returning to Berlin, he began to study Spanish so he could read some of his favorite authors in their original language. He likedPedro Calderón de la Barca,Lope de Vega,Miguel de Cervantes,and especiallyBaltasar Gracián.[16]: 420 He also made failed attempts to publish his translations of their works. A few attempts to revive his lectures—again scheduled at the same time as Hegel's—also failed, as did his inquiries about relocating to other universities.[16]: 429–432 

During his Berlin years, Schopenhauer occasionally mentioned his desire to marry and have a family.[16]: 404,432 For a while he was unsuccessfully courting 17-year-old Flora Weiss, who was 22 years younger than himself.[16]: 433 His unpublished writings from that time show that he was already very critical ofmonogamybut still not advocatingpolygyny—instead musing about apolyamorousrelationship that he called "tetragamy".[16]: 404–408 He had an on-and-off relationship with a young dancer,Caroline Richter(she also used the surname Medon after one of her ex-lovers).[16]: 403 They met when he was 33 and she was 19 and working at the Berlin Opera. She had already had numerous lovers and a son out of wedlock, and later gave birth to another son, this time to an unnamed foreign diplomat (she soon had another pregnancy but the child was stillborn).[16]: 403–404 As Schopenhauer was preparing to escape from Berlin in 1831, due to acholeraepidemic, he offered to take her with him on the condition that she left her young son behind.[16]: 404 She refused and he went alone; in his will he left her a significant sum of money, but insisted that it should not be spent in any way on her second son.[16]: 404 

Schopenhauer claimed that, in his last year in Berlin, he had aprophetic dreamthat urged him to escape from the city.[16]: 436 As he arrived in his new home inFrankfurt,he supposedly had anothersupernatural experience,an apparition of his dead father and his mother, who was still alive.[16]: 436 This experience led him to spend some time investigatingparanormalphenomena andmagic.He was quite critical of the available studies and claimed that they were mostly ignorant or fraudulent, but he did believe that there are authentic cases of such phenomena and tried to explain them through his metaphysics as manifestations of the will.[16]: 437–452 

Upon his arrival in Frankfurt, he experienced a period of depression and declining health.[16]: 454 He renewed his correspondence with his mother, and she seemed concerned that he might commit suicide like his father.[16]: 454–457 By now Johanna and Adele were living very modestly. Johanna's writing did not bring her much income, and her popularity was waning.[16]: 458 Their correspondence remained reserved, and Arthur seemed undisturbed by her death in 1838.[16]: 460 His relationship with his sister grew closer and he corresponded with her until she died in 1849.[16]: 463 

In July 1832, Schopenhauer left Frankfurt forMannheimbut returned in July 1833 to remain there for the rest of his life, except for a few short journeys.[16]: 464 He lived alone except for a succession of petpoodlesnamedAtmanand Butz. In 1836, he publishedOn the Will in Nature.In 1838, he sent his essay "On the Freedom of the Will"to the contest of theRoyal Norwegian Society of Sciencesin 1838 and won the prize in 1839. He sent another essay, "On the Basis of Morality",to theRoyal Danish Society of Sciencesin 1839, but did not win the (1840) prize despite being the only contestant.[33]The Society was appalled that several distinguished contemporary philosophers were mentioned in a very offensive manner, and claimed that the essay missed the point of the set topic and that the arguments were inadequate.[16]: 483 Schopenhauer, who had been very confident that he would win, was enraged by this rejection. He published both essays asThe Two Basic Problems of Ethics.The first edition, published September 1840 but with an 1841 date, again failed to draw attention to his philosophy. In the preface to the second edition, in 1860, he was still pouring insults on the Royal Danish Society.[16]: 484 Two years later, after some negotiations, he managed to convince his publisher, Brockhaus, to print the second, updated edition ofThe World as Will and Representation.That book was again mostly ignored and the few reviews were mixed or negative.

Schopenhauer began to attract some followers, mostly outside academia, among practical professionals (several of them were lawyers) who pursued private philosophical studies. He jokingly referred to them as "evangelists" and "apostles".[16]: 504 One of the most active early followers wasJulius Frauenstädt,who wrote numerous articles promoting Schopenhauer's philosophy. He was also instrumental in finding another publisher after Brockhaus declined to publishParerga and Paralipomena,believing that it would be another failure.[16]: 506 Though Schopenhauer later stopped corresponding with him, claiming that he did not adhere closely enough to his ideas, Frauenstädt continued to promote Schopenhauer's work.[16]: 507–508 They renewed their communication in 1859 and Schopenhauer named him heir for his literary estate.[16]: 508 Frauenstädt also became the editor of the first collected works of Schopenhauer.[16]: 506 

In 1848, Schopenhauer witnessedviolent upheavalin Frankfurt after GeneralHans Adolf Erdmann von Auerswaldand PrinceFelix Lichnowskywere murdered. He became worried for his own safety and property.[16]: 514 Even earlier in life he had had such worries and kept a sword and loaded pistols near his bed to defend himself from thieves.[16]: 465 He gave a friendly welcome to Austrian soldiers who wanted to shoot revolutionaries from his window and as they were leaving he gave one of the officers his opera glasses to help him monitor rebels.[16]: 514 The rebellion passed without any loss to Schopenhauer and he later praisedAlfred I, Prince of Windisch-Grätzfor restoring order.[16]: 515 He even modified his will, leaving a large part of his property to a Prussian fund that helped soldiers who became invalids while fighting rebellion in 1848 or the families of soldiers who died in battle.[16]: 517 AsYoung Hegelianswere advocating change and progress, Schopenhauer claimed that misery is natural for humans and that, even if some utopian society were established, people would still fight each other out of boredom, or would starve due to overpopulation.[16]: 515 

1855 painting of Schopenhauer byJules Lunteschütz

In 1851, Schopenhauer publishedParerga and Paralipomena,which contains essays that are supplementary to his main work. It was his first successful, widely read book, partly due to the work of his disciples who wrote praising reviews.[16]: 524 The essays that proved most popular were the ones that actually did not contain the basic philosophical ideas of his system.[16]: 539 Many academic philosophers considered him a great stylist and cultural critic but did not take his philosophy seriously.[16]: 539 His early critics liked to point out similarities of his ideas to those of Fichte and Schelling,[16]: 381–386 or to claim that there were numerous contradictions in his philosophy.[16]: 381–386, 537 Both criticisms enraged Schopenhauer. He was becoming less interested in intellectual fights, but encouraged his disciples to do so.[16]: 525 His private notes and correspondence show that he acknowledged some of the criticisms regarding contradictions, inconsistencies, and vagueness in his philosophy, but claimed that he was not concerned about harmony and agreement in his propositions[16]: 394 and that some of his ideas should not be taken literally but instead as metaphors.[16]: 510 

Academic philosophers were also starting to notice his work. In 1856, the University of Leipzig sponsored an essay contest about Schopenhauer's philosophy, which was won byRudolf Seydel's very critical essay.[16]: 536 Schopenhauer's friendJules Lunteschützmade the first of his four portraits of him—which Schopenhauer did not particularly like—which was soon sold to a wealthy landowner, Carl Ferdinand Wiesike, who built a house to display it. Schopenhauer seemed flattered and amused by this, and would claim that it was his first chapel.[16]: 540 As his fame increased, copies of paintings and photographs of him were being sold and admirers were visiting the places where he had lived and written his works. People visited Frankfurt'sEnglischer Hofto observe him dining. Admirers gave him gifts and asked for autographs.[16]: 541 He complained that he still felt isolated due to his not very social nature and the fact that many of his good friends had already died from old age.[16]: 542 

Grave at theHauptfriedhofinFrankfurt

He remained healthy in his own old age, which he attributed to regular walks no matter the weather and always getting enough sleep.[16]: 544–545 He had a great appetite and could read without glasses, but hishearinghad been declining since his youth and he developed problems withrheumatism.[16]: 545 He remained active and lucid, continued his reading, writing and correspondence until his death.[16]: 545 The numerous notes that he made during these years, amongst others on aging, were publishedposthumouslyunder the titleSenilia.In the spring of 1860 his health began to decline, and he experienced shortness of breath and heart palpitations; in September he suffered inflammation of the lungs and, although he was starting to recover, he remained very weak.[16]: 546 The last friend to visit him was Wilhelm Gwinner; according to him, Schopenhauer was concerned that he would not be able to finish his planned additions toParerga and Paralipomenabut was at peace with dying.[16]: 546–547 He died ofpulmonary-respiratory failure[34]on 21 September 1860 while sitting at home on his couch. He died at the age of 72 and had a funeral conducted by a Lutheran minister.[35][36]

Philosophy[edit]

Theory of perception[edit]

In November 1813Goetheinvited Schopenhauer to help him on hisTheory of Colours.Although Schopenhauer considered colour theory a minor matter,[37]he accepted the invitation out of admiration for Goethe. Nevertheless, these investigations led him to his most important discovery in epistemology: finding a demonstration for thea priorinature of causality.

Kant openly admitted that it wasHume's skeptical assault on causality that motivated the critical investigations inCritique of Pure Reasonand gave an elaborate proof to show that causality isa priori.AfterG. E. Schulzehad made it plausible that Kant had not disproven Hume's skepticism, it was up to those loyal to Kant's project to prove this important matter.

The difference between the approaches of Kant and Schopenhauer was this: Kant simply declared that the empirical content of perception is "given" to us from outside, an expression with which Schopenhauer often expressed his dissatisfaction.[38]He, on the other hand, was occupied with the questions: how do we get this empirical content of perception; how is it possible to comprehend subjective sensations "limited to my skin" as the objective perception of things that lie "outside" of me?[39]

The sensations in the hand of a man born blind, on feeling an object of cubic shape, are quite uniform and the same on all sides and in every direction: the edges, it is true, press upon a smaller portion of his hand, still nothing at all like a cube is contained in these sensations. His Understanding draws the immediate and intuitive conclusion from the resistance felt, that this resistance must have a cause, which then presents itself through that conclusion as a hard body; and through the movements of his arms in feeling the object, while the hand's sensation remains unaltered, he constructs the cubic shape in Space. If the representation of a cause and of Space, together with their laws, had not already existed within him, the image of a cube could never have proceeded from those successive sensations in his hand.[40]

Causality is therefore not an empirical concept drawn from objective perceptions, as Hume had maintained; instead, as Kant had said, objective perception presupposes knowledge of causality.[41]

By this intellectual operation, comprehending every effect in our sensory organs as having an external cause, the external world arises. With vision, finding the cause is essentially simplified due to light acting in straight lines. We are seldom conscious of the process that interprets the double sensation in both eyes as coming from one object, that inverts the impressions on the retinas, and that uses the change in the apparent position of an object relative to more distant objects provided by binocular vision to perceive depth and distance.

Schopenhauer stresses the importance of the intellectual nature of perception; the senses furnish the raw material by which the intellect produces the world as representation. He set out his theory of perception for the first time inOn Vision and Colors,[42]and, in the subsequent editions ofFourfold Root,an extensive exposition is given in § 21.

The world as representation[edit]

Schopenhauer saw his philosophy as an extension of Kant's, and used the results of Kantian epistemological investigation (transcendental idealism) as starting point for his own. Kant had argued that theempiricalworld is merely a complex of appearances whose existence and connection occur only in ourmental representations.[43]Schopenhauer did not deny that the external world existed empirically but followed Kant in claiming that our knowledge and experience of the world is always indirect.[44]Schopenhauer reiterates this in the first sentence of his main work: "The world is my representation (Die Welt ist meine Vorstellung) ". Everything that there is for cognition (the entire world) exists simply as an object in relation to a subject—a 'representation' to a subject. Everything that belongs to the world is, therefore, 'subject-dependent'. In Book One ofThe World as Will and Representation,Schopenhauer considers the world from this angle—that is, insofar as it is representation.

Kant had previously argued that we perceive reality as something spatial and temporal not because reality is inherently spatial and temporal, but because that is how our minds operate in perceiving an object. Therefore, understanding objects in space and time represents our 'contribution' to an experience. For Schopenhauer, Kant's 'greatest service' lay in the 'differentiation betweenphenomenaand the thing-in-itself (noumena), based on the proof that between everything and us there is always a perceiving mind.' In other words, Kant's primary achievement is to demonstrate that instead of being a blank slate where reality merely reveals its character, the mind, with sensory support, actively participates in constructing reality. Thus, Schopenhauer believed that Kant had shown that the everyday world of experience, and indeed the entire material world related to space and time, is merely 'appearance' or 'phenomena,' entirely distinct from the thing-in-itself.'[45]

The world as will[edit]

In Book Two ofThe World as Will and Representation,Schopenhauer considers what the world is beyond the aspect of it that appears to us—that is, the aspect of the world beyond representation, the world considered "in-itself"or"noumena",its inner essence. The very being in-itself of all things, Schopenhauer argues, is will (Wille). The empirical world that appears to us as representation has plurality and is ordered in a spatio-temporal framework. The world as thing in-itself must exist outside the subjective forms of space and time. Although the world manifests itself to our experience as a multiplicity of objects (the "objectivation" of the will), each element of this multiplicity has the same blind essence striving towards existence and life. Human rationality is merely a secondary phenomenon that does not distinguish humanity from the rest of nature at the fundamental, essential level. The advanced cognitive abilities of human beings, Schopenhauer argues, serve the ends of willing—an illogical, directionless, ceaseless striving that condemns the human individual to a life of suffering unredeemed by any final purpose. Schopenhauer's philosophy of the will as the essential reality behind the world as representation is often calledmetaphysical voluntarism.[3]

For Schopenhauer, understanding the world as will leads to ethical concerns (see theethics section belowfor further detail), which he explores in the Fourth Book ofThe World as Will and Representationand again in his two prize essays on ethics,On the Freedom of the WillandOn the Basis of Morality.No individual human actions are free, Schopenhauer argues, because they are events in the world of appearance and thus are subject to the principle of sufficient reason: a person's actions are a necessary consequence of motives and the given character of the individual human. Necessity extends to the actions of human beings just as it does to every other appearance, and thus we cannot speak of freedom of individual willing. Albert Einstein quoted the Schopenhauerian idea that "a man candoas he will, but notwillas he will. "[46]Yet the will as thing in-itself is free, as it exists beyond the realm of representation and thus is not constrained by any of the forms of necessity that are part of the principle of sufficient reason.

According to Schopenhauer, salvation from our miserable existence can come through the will's being "tranquillized" by the metaphysical insight that reveals individuality to be merely an illusion. The saint or 'great soul' intuitively "recognizes the whole, comprehends its essence, and finds that it is constantly passing away, caught up in vain strivings, inner conflict, and perpetual suffering".[47]The negation of the will, in other words, stems from the insight that the world in-itself (free from the forms of space and time) is one.Asceticpractices, Schopenhauer remarks, are used to aid the will's "self-abolition", which brings about a blissful, redemptive "will-less" state of emptiness that is free from striving or suffering.

Art and aesthetics[edit]

In his main work, Schopenhauer praised theDutch Golden Age artists,who "directed such purely objective perception to the most insignificant objects, and set up a lasting monument of their objectivity and spiritual peace in paintings ofstill life.The aesthetic beholder does not contemplate this without emotion. "[48]

For Schopenhauer, human "willing" —desiring, craving, etc.—is at the root ofsuffering.A temporary way to escape this pain is through aesthetic contemplation. Here one moves away from ordinary cognizance of individual things to cognizance of eternal PlatonicIdeas—in other words, cognizance that is free from the service of will. In aesthetic contemplation, one no longer perceives an object of perception as something from which one is separated; rather "it is as if the object alone existed without anyone perceiving it, and one can thus no longer separate the perceiver from the perception, but the two have become one, the entirety of consciousness entirely filled and occupied by a single perceptual image".[49]Subject and object are no longer distinguishable, and theIdeacomes to the fore.

From this aesthetic immersion, one is no longer an individual who suffers as a result of servitude to one's individual will but, rather, becomes a "pure, will-less, painless, timeless, subject of cognition". The pure, will-less subject of cognition is cognizant only of Ideas, not individual things: this is a kind of cognition that is unconcerned with relations between objects according to the Principle of Sufficient Reason (time, space, cause and effect) and instead involves complete absorption in the object.

Art is the practical consequence of this brief aesthetic contemplation, since it attempts to depict the essence/pure Ideas of the world. Music, for Schopenhauer, is the purest form of art because it is the one that depicts the will itself without it appearing as subject to the Principle of Sufficient Reason, therefore as an individual object. According toDaniel Albright,"Schopenhauer thought thatmusicwas the only art that did not merely copy ideas, but actually embodied the will itself ".[50]He deemed music a timeless, universal language comprehended everywhere, that can imbue global enthusiasm, if in possession of a significant melody.[51]

Mathematics[edit]

Schopenhauer'srealistviews on mathematics are evident in his criticism of contemporaneous attempts to prove theparallel postulateinEuclidean geometry.Writing shortly before the discovery ofhyperbolic geometrydemonstrated the logical independence of theaxiom—and long before thegeneral theory of relativityrevealed that it does not necessarily express a property of physical space—Schopenhauer criticized mathematicians for trying to use indirectconceptsto prove what he held was directly evident fromintuitive perception.

The Euclidean method of demonstration has brought forth from its own womb its most striking parody and caricature in the famous controversy over the theory ofparallels,and in the attempts, repeated every year, to prove the eleventh axiom (also known as the fifth postulate). The axiom asserts, and that indeed through the indirect criterion of a third intersecting line, that two lines inclined to each other (for this is the precise meaning of "less than two right angles" ), if produced far enough, must meet. Now this truth is supposed to be too complicated to pass as self-evident, and therefore needs a proof; but no such proof can be produced, just because there is nothing more immediate.[52]

Throughout his writings,[53]Schopenhauer criticized the logical derivation of philosophies and mathematics from mere concepts, instead of from intuitive perceptions.

In fact, it seems to me that the logical method is in this way reduced to an absurdity. But it is precisely through the controversies over this, together with the futile attempts to demonstrate thedirectlycertain as merelyindirectlycertain, that the independence and clearness of intuitive evidence appear in contrast with the uselessness and difficulty of logical proof, a contrast as instructive as it is amusing. The direct certainty will not be admitted here, just because it is no merely logical certainty following from the concept, and thus resting solely on the relation of predicate to subject, according to the principle of contradiction. But that eleventh axiom regarding parallel lines is asynthetic propositiona priori,and as such has the guarantee of pure, not empirical, perception; this perception is just as immediate and certain as is theprinciple of contradictionitself, from which all proofs originally derive their certainty. At bottom this holds good of every geometrical theorem...

Although Schopenhauer could see no justification for trying to prove Euclid's parallel postulate, he did see a reason for examining another of Euclid's axioms.[54]

It surprises me that the eighth axiom,[55]"Figures that coincide with one another are equal to one another", is not rather attacked. For"coinciding with one another"is either a meretautology,or something quiteempirical,belonging not to pure intuition or perception, but to external sensuous experience. Thus it presupposes mobility of the figures, butmatteralone is movable inspace.Consequently, this reference to coincidence with one another forsakes pure space, the sole element ofgeometry,in order to pass over to the material and empirical.[52]

This followsKant's reasoning.[56]

Ethics[edit]

Schopenhauer asserts that the task of ethics is not to prescribe moral actions that ought to be done, but to investigate moral actions. As such, he states that philosophy is always theoretical: its task to explain what is given.[57]

According to Kant's transcendental idealism, space and time are forms of our sensibility in which phenomena appear in multiplicity. Realityin itselfis free from multiplicity, not in the sense that an object is one, but that it is outside thepossibilityof multiplicity. Two individuals, though they appear distinct, are in-themselves not distinct.[58]

Appearances are entirely subordinated to theprinciple of sufficient reason.The egoistic individual who focuses his aims on his own interests has to deal with empirical laws as well as he can.

What is relevant for ethics are individuals who can act against their own self-interest. If we take a man who suffers when he sees his fellow men living in poverty and consequently uses a significant part of his income to supporttheirneeds instead of hisownpleasures, then the simplest way to describe this is that he makesless distinction between himselfand others than is usually made.[59]

Regarding how thingsappearto us, the egoist asserts a gap between two individuals, but the altruist experiences the sufferings of others as his own. In the same way a compassionate man cannot hurt animals, though they appear as distinct from himself.

What motivates the altruist is compassion. The suffering of others is for him not a cold matter to which he is indifferent, but he feels connectiveness to all beings. Compassion is thus the basis of morality.[60]

Eternal justice[edit]

Schopenhauer calls the principle through which multiplicity appears theprincipium individuationis.When we behold nature we see that it is a cruel battle for existence. Individual manifestations of the will can maintain themselves only at the expense of others—the will, as the only thing that exists, has no other option but to devour itself to experience pleasure. This is a fundamental characteristic of the will, and cannot be circumvented.[61]

Unlike temporal or human justice, which requires time to repay an evil deed and "has its seat in the state, as requiting and punishing",[62]eternal justice "rules not the state but the world, is not dependent upon human institutions, is not subject to chance and deception, is not uncertain, wavering, and erring, but infallible, fixed, and sure".[62]Eternal justice is not retributive, because retribution requires time. There are no delays or reprieves. Instead, punishment is tied to the offence, "to the point where the two become one.... Tormenter and tormented are one. The [Tormenter] errs in that he believes he is not a partaker in the suffering; the [tormented], in that he believes he is not a partaker in the guilt."[62]

Suffering is the moral outcome of our attachment to pleasure. Schopenhauer deemed that this truth was expressed by the Christian dogma oforiginal sinand, in Eastern religions, by thedogma of rebirth.

Quietism[edit]

He who sees through theprincipium individuationisand comprehends sufferingin generalas his own will see suffering everywhere and, instead of fighting for the happiness of his individual manifestation, will abhor life itself since he knows that it is inseparably connected with suffering. For him, a happy individual life in a world of suffering is like a beggar who dreams one night that he is a king.[63]

Those who have experienced this intuitive knowledge cannot affirm life, but exhibit asceticism and quietism, meaning that they are no longer sensitive to motives, are not concerned about their individual welfare, and accept without resistance the evil that others inflict on them. They welcome poverty and neither seek nor flee death.[63]Schopenhauer referred to asceticism as the denial of the will to live.

Human life is a ceaseless struggle for satisfaction and, instead of continuing their struggle, ascetics break it. It does not matter if these ascetics adhere to the dogmata of Christianity or toDharmic religions,since their way of living is the result of intuitive knowledge.

TheChristian mysticand the teacher of theVedanta philosophyagree in this respect also, they both regard all outward works and religious exercises as superfluous for him who has attained to perfection. So much agreement in the case of such different ages and nations is a practical proof that what is expressed here is not, as optimistic dullness likes to assert, an eccentricity and perversity of the mind, but an essential side of human nature, which only appears so rarely because of its excellence.[63]

Psychology[edit]

Philosophers have not traditionally been impressed by the necessity of sex, but Schopenhauer addressed sex and related concepts forthrightly:

... one ought rather to be surprised that a thing [sex] which plays throughout so important a part in human life has hitherto practically been disregarded by philosophers altogether, and lies before us as raw and untreated material.[64]

He named a force within man that he felt took invariable precedence over reason: the Will to Live or Will to Life (Wille zum Leben), defined as an inherent drive within human beings, and all creatures, to stay alive; a force that inveigles[65]us into reproducing.

Schopenhauer refused to conceive of love as either trifling or accidental, but rather understood it as an immensely powerful force that lay unseen within man'spsyche,guaranteeing the quality of the human race:

The ultimate aim of all love affairs... is more important than all other aims in man's life; and therefore it is quite worthy of the profound seriousness with which everyone pursues it. What is decided by it is nothing less than the composition of the next generation...[66]

It has often been argued that Schopenhauer's thoughts on sexuality foreshadowed thetheory of evolution,a claim met with satisfaction byDarwinas he included a quotation from Schopenhauer in hisDescent of Man.[67]This has also been noted aboutFreud's concepts of thelibidoand theunconscious mind,andevolutionary psychologyin general.[68]

Political and social thought[edit]

Politics[edit]

Bust inFrankfurt

Schopenhauer's politics were an echo of his system of ethics, which he elucidated in detail in hisDie beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik(the two essaysOn the Freedom of the WillandOn the Basis of Morality).

In occasional political comments in hisParerga and ParalipomenaandManuscript Remains,Schopenhauer described himself as a proponent oflimited government.Schopenhauer shared the view ofThomas Hobbeson the necessity of the state and state action to check the innate destructive tendencies of our species. He also defended the independence of the legislative, judicial and executive branches of power, and a monarch as an impartial element able to practise justice (in a practical and everyday sense, not a cosmological one).[69]

He declared that monarchy is "natural to man in almost the same way as it is to bees and ants, to cranes in flight, to wandering elephants, to wolves in a pack in search of prey, and to other animals".[70]Intellect in monarchies, he writes, always has "much better chances against stupidity, its implacable and ever-present foe, than it has in republics; but this is a great advantage."[70]On the other hand, Schopenhauer disparagedrepublicanismas being "as unnatural to man as it is unfavorable to higher intellectual life and thus to the arts and sciences".[71]

By his own admission, Schopenhauer did not give much thought to politics, and several times he wrote proudly of how little attention he paid "to political affairs of [his] day". In a life that spanned several revolutions in French and German government, and a few continent-shaking wars, he maintained his position of "minding not the times but the eternities". He wrote many disparaging remarks about Germany and the Germans. A typical example is: "For a German it is even good to have somewhat lengthy words in his mouth, for he thinks slowly, and they give him time to reflect."[72]

Punishment[edit]

The State, Schopenhauer claimed, punishes criminals to prevent future crimes. It places "beside every possible motive for committing a wrong a more powerful motive for leaving it undone, in the inescapable punishment. Accordingly, the criminal code is as complete a register as possible of counter-motives to all criminal actions that can possibly be imagined..."[73]He claimed that this doctrine was not original to him but had appeared in the writings ofPlato,[74]Seneca,Hobbes,Pufendorf,andAnselm Feuerbach.

Races and religions[edit]

Schopenhauer attributed civilizational primacy to the northern "white races" due to their sensitivity and creativity (except for the ancient Egyptians and Hindus, whom he saw as equal):

The highest civilization and culture, apart from theancient HindusandEgyptians,are found exclusively among the white races; and even with many dark peoples, the ruling caste or race is fairer in colour than the rest and has, therefore, evidently immigrated, for example, theBrahmans,theIncas,and the rulers of theSouth Sea Islands.All this is due to the fact that necessity is the mother of invention because those tribes that emigrated early to the north, and there gradually became white, had to develop all their intellectual powers and invent and perfect all the arts in their struggle with need, want and misery, which in their many forms were brought about by the climate. This they had to do in order to make up for the parsimony of nature and out of it all came their high civilization.[75]

Schopenhauer was ferventlyopposed to slavery.Speaking of the treatment of slaves in theslave-holding states of the United States,he condemned "those devils in human form, those bigoted, church-going, strict sabbath-observing scoundrels, especially the Anglican parsons among them" for how they "treat their innocent black brothers who through violence and injustice have fallen into their devil's claws". The slave-holding states of North America, Schopenhauer writes, are a "disgrace to the whole of humanity".[76]

Schopenhauer also maintained a marked metaphysical and politicalanti-Judaism.He argued that Christianity constituted a revolt against what he styled the materialistic basis of Judaism, exhibiting an Indian-influenced ethics reflecting theAryan-Vedictheme of spiritual self-conquest. He saw this as opposed to the ignorant drive toward earthly utopianism and superficiality of a worldly "Jewish" spirit:

[Judaism] is, therefore, the crudest and poorest of all religions and consists merely in an absurd and revoltingtheism.It amounts to this that theκύριος['Lord'],who has created the world, desires to be worshipped and adored; and so above all he is jealous, is envious of his colleagues, of all the other gods; if sacrifices are made to them he is furious and his Jews have a bad time... It is most deplorable that this religion has become the basis of the prevailing religion of Europe; for it is a religion without any metaphysical tendency. While all other religions endeavor to explain to the people by symbols the metaphysical significance of life, the religion of the Jews is entirely immanent and furnishes nothing but a mere war-cry in the struggle with other nations.[77]

Women[edit]

In his 1851 essay "On Women", Schopenhauer expressed opposition to what he called "Teutonico-Christian stupidity" of "reflexive, unexamined reverence for the female (abgeschmackten Weiberveneration) ".[78]He wrote: "Women are directly fitted for acting as the nurses and teachers of our early childhood by the fact that they are themselves childish, frivolous and short-sighted." He opined that women are deficient in artistic faculties and sense of justice, and expressed his opposition tomonogamy.[79]He claimed that "woman is by nature meant to obey". The essay does give some compliments: "women are decidedly more sober in their judgment than [men] are", and are more sympathetic to the suffering of others.

Schopenhauer's writings influenced many, fromFriedrich Nietzscheto nineteenth-centuryfeminists.[80]Hisbiologicalanalysis of the difference between the sexes, and their separate roles in the struggle for survival and reproduction, anticipates some of the claims that were later ventured bysociobiologistsandevolutionary psychologists.[81]

When the elderly Schopenhauer sat fora sculpture portraitby the Prussian sculptorElisabet Neyin 1859, he was much impressed by the young woman's wit and independence, as well as by her skill as a visual artist.[82]After his time with Ney, he told Richard Wagner's friendMalwida von Meysenbug:"I have not yet spoken my last word about women. I believe that if a woman succeeds in withdrawing from the mass, or rather raising herself above the mass, she grows ceaselessly and more than a man."[83]

Pederasty[edit]

In the third, expanded edition ofThe World as Will and Representation(1859), Schopenhauer added an appendix to his chapter on theMetaphysics of Sexual Love.He wrote thatpederastyhas the benefit of preventing ill-begotten children. Concerning this, he stated that "the vice we are considering appears to work directly against the aims and ends of nature, and that in a matter that is all important and of the greatest concern to her it must in fact serve these very aims, although only indirectly, as a means for preventing greater evils."[84] Schopenhauer ends the appendix with the statement that "by expounding these paradoxical ideas, I wanted to grant to the professors of philosophy a small favour. I have done so by giving them the opportunity of slandering me by saying that I defend and commend pederasty."[85]

Heredity and eugenics[edit]

Schopenhauer at age 58 on 16 May 1846

Schopenhauer viewed personality andintellectas inherited. He quotesHorace's saying, "From the brave and good are the brave descended" (Odes,iv, 4, 29) and Shakespeare's line fromCymbeline,"Cowards father cowards, and base things sire base" (IV, 2) to reinforce his hereditarian argument.[86] Mechanistically, Schopenhauer believed that a person inherits his intellect through his mother, and personal character through the father.[87]This belief in heritability of traits informed Schopenhauer's view of love—placing it at the highest level of importance. For Schopenhauer the "final aim of all love intrigues, be they comic or tragic, is really of more importance than all other ends in human life. What it all turns upon is nothing less than the composition of the next generation.... It is not the weal or woe of any one individual, but that of the human race to come, which is here at stake." This view of the importance for the species of whom we choose to love was reflected in his views oneugenicsor good breeding. Here Schopenhauer wrote:

With our knowledge of the complete unalterability both of character and of mental faculties, we are led to the view that a real and thorough improvement of the human race might be reached not so much from outside as from within, not so much by theory and instruction as rather by the path of generation. Plato had something of the kind in mind when, in the fifth book of hisRepublic,he explained his plan for increasing and improving his warrior caste. If we couldcastrateall scoundrels and stick all stupid geese in a convent, and give men of noble character a wholeharem,and procure men, and indeed thorough men, for all girls of intellect and understanding, then a generation would soon arise which would produce a better age than that ofPericles.[88]

In another context, Schopenhauer reiterated his eugenic thesis: "If you want Utopian plans, I would say: the only solution to the problem is thedespotismof the wise and noble members of a genuine aristocracy, a genuine nobility, achieved bymatingthe most magnanimous men with the cleverest and most gifted women. This proposal constitutes my Utopia and my Platonic Republic. "[89]Analysts (e.g.,Keith Ansell-Pearson) have suggested that Schopenhauer's anti-egalitarianistsentiment and his support for eugenics influenced the neo-aristocratic philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche, who initially considered Schopenhauer his mentor.[90]

Animal rights[edit]

As a consequence of hismonisticphilosophy, Schopenhauer was very concerned about animal welfare and rights.[91][6]For him, all individual animals, including humans, are essentially phenomenal manifestations of the one underlying Will. For him the word "will" designates force, power, impulse, energy, and desire; it is the closest word we have that can signify both the essence of all external things and our own direct, inner experience. Since every living thing possesses will, humans and animals are fundamentally the same and can recognize themselves in each other.[92]For this reason, he claimed that a good person would have sympathy for animals, who are our fellow sufferers.

Compassion for animals is intimately associated with goodness of character, and it may be confidently asserted that he who is cruel to living creatures cannot be a good man.

Nothing leads more definitely to a recognition of the identity of the essential nature in animal and human phenomena than a study of zoology and anatomy.

— On the Basis of Morality,chapter 8[93]

The assumption that animals are without rights and the illusion that our treatment of them has no moral significance is a positively outrageous example of Western crudity and barbarity. Universal compassion is the only guarantee of morality.

— On the Basis of Morality,chapter 8[94]

In 1841, he praised the establishment in London of theSociety for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals,and in Philadelphia of the Animals' Friends Society. Schopenhauer went so far as to protest using the pronoun "it" in reference to animals because that led to treatment of them as though they were inanimate things.[95]To reinforce his points, Schopenhauer referred to anecdotal reports of the look in the eyes of a monkey who had been shot[96]and also the grief of a baby elephant whose mother had been killed by a hunter.[97]

Schopenhauer was very attached to his succession of pet poodles. He criticizedSpinoza's[98]belief that animals are a mere means for the satisfaction of humans.[99][100]Tim Madigan wrote that despite all of his bombast, Schopenhauer was a sympathetic character who had concerns for the suffering of animals.

The greatest benefit conferred by the railways is that they spare millions of draught-horses their miserable existences.

— Essays and Aphorisms,p. 171[101]

Intellectual interests and affinities[edit]

Indology[edit]

Photo of Schopenhauer, 1852

Schopenhauer read the Latin translation of theancient Hindu texts,theUpanishads,translated by French writerAnquetil du Perron[102]from the Persian translation of PrinceDara ShukohentitledSirre-Akbar( "The Great Secret" ). He was so impressed by itsphilosophythat he called it "the production of the highest human wisdom", and believed it contained superhuman concepts. Schopenhauer considered India as "the land of the most ancient and most pristine wisdom, the place from whichEuropeanscould trace their descent and the tradition by which they had been influenced in so many decisive ways ",[102]and regarded theUpanishadsas "the most profitable and elevating reading which [...] is possible in the world. It has been the solace of my life, and will be the solace of my death."[102]

Schopenhauer was first introduced to Anquetil du Perron's translation by Friedrich Majer in 1814.[102]They met during the winter of 1813–1814 inWeimarat the home of Schopenhauer's mother, according to the biographer Safranski. Majer was a follower ofHerder,and an earlyIndologist.Schopenhauer did not begin serious study of the Indic texts until the summer of 1814. Safranski maintains that, between 1815 and 1817, Schopenhauer had another important cross-pollination with Indian thought inDresden.This was through his neighbor of two years,Karl Christian Friedrich Krause.Krause was then a minor and rather unorthodox philosopher who attempted to mix his own ideas with ancient Indian wisdom. Krause had also masteredSanskrit,unlike Schopenhauer, and they developed a professional relationship. It was from Krause that Schopenhauer learnedmeditationand received the closest thing to expert advice concerning Indian thought.[103]

The view of things [...] that all plurality is only apparent, that in the endless series of individuals, passing simultaneously and successively into and out of life, generation after generation, age after age, there is but one and the same entity really existing, which is present and identical in all alike;—this theory, I say, was of course known long before Kant; indeed, it may be carried back to the remotest antiquity. It is the Alpha and Omega of the oldest book in the world, the sacredVedas,whose dogmatic part, or rather esoteric teaching, is found in the Upanishads. There, in almost every page this profound doctrine lies enshrined; with tireless repetition, in countless adaptations, by many varied parables and similes it is expounded and inculcated.

— On the Basis of Morality,chapter 4[104]

The bookOupnekhat(Upanishad) always lay open on his table, and he invariably studied it before going to bed. He called the opening up ofSanskrit literature"the greatest gift of our century", and predicted that the philosophy and knowledge of the Upanishads would become the cherished faith of the West.[105]Most noticeable, in the case of Schopenhauer's work, was the significance of theChandogya Upanishad,whoseMahāvākya,Tat Tvam Asi,is mentioned throughoutThe World as Will and Representation.[106]

Buddhism[edit]

Schopenhauer noted a correspondence between his doctrines and theFour Noble TruthsofBuddhism.[107]Similarities centered on the principles that life involves suffering, that suffering is caused by desire (taṇhā), and that the extinction of desire leads to liberation. Thus three of the four "truths of the Buddha" correspond to Schopenhauer's doctrine of the will.[108]In Buddhism, while greed and lust are always unskillful, desire is ethically variable – it can be skillful, unskillful, or neutral.[109]

For Schopenhauer, will hadontologicalprimacy over theintellect;desire is prior to thought. Schopenhauer felt this was similar to notions ofpuruṣārthaor goals of life inVedāntaHinduism.

In Schopenhauer's philosophy, denial of the will is attained by:

  • personal experience of an extremely great suffering that leads to loss of the will to live; or
  • knowledge of the essential nature of life in the world through observation of the suffering of other people.

Buddhistnirvāṇais not equivalent to the condition that Schopenhauer described as denial of the will. Nirvāṇa is not the extinguishing of thepersonas some Western scholars have thought, but only the "extinguishing" (the literal meaning of nirvana) of the flames of greed, hatred, and delusion that assail a person's character.[110]Schopenhauer made the following statement in his discussion of religions:[111]

If I wished to take the results of my philosophy as the standard of truth, I should have to concede to Buddhism pre-eminence over the others. In any case, it must be a pleasure to me to see my doctrine in such close agreement with a religion that the majority of men on earth hold as their own, for this numbers far more followers than any other. And this agreement must be yet the more pleasing to me, inasmuch asin my philosophizing I have certainly not been under its influence[emphasis added]. For up till 1818, when my work appeared, there was to be found in Europe only a very few accounts of Buddhism.[112]

Buddhist philosopherKeiji Nishitanisought to distance Buddhism from Schopenhauer.[113]While Schopenhauer's philosophy may sound rather mystical in such a summary, hismethodologywas resolutelyempirical,rather than speculative or transcendental:

Philosophy... is a science, and as such has no articles of faith; accordingly, in it nothing can be assumed as existing except what is either positively given empirically, or demonstrated through indubitable conclusions.[114]

Also note:

This actual world of what is knowable, in which we are and which is in us, remains both the material and the limit of our consideration.[115]

The argument that Buddhism affected Schopenhauer's philosophy more than any otherDharmicfaith loses credence since he did not begin a serious study of Buddhism until after the publication ofThe World as Will and Representationin 1818.[116]Scholars have started to revise earlier views about Schopenhauer's discovery of Buddhism. Proof of early interest and influence appears in Schopenhauer's 1815–16 notes (transcribed and translated by Urs App) about Buddhism. They are included in a recent case study that traces Schopenhauer's interest in Buddhism and documents its influence.[117]Other scholarly work questions how similar Schopenhauer's philosophy actually is to Buddhism.[118]

Magic and occultism[edit]

Some traditions inWestern esotericismandparapsychologyinterested Schopenhauer and influenced his philosophical theories. He praisedanimal magnetismas evidence for the reality of magic in hisOn the Will in Nature,and went so far as to accept the division of magic intoleft-hand and right-hand magic,although he doubted the existence of demons.[119]

Schopenhauer grounded magic in the Will and claimed all forms of magical transformation depended on the human Will, not on ritual. This theory notably parallelsAleister Crowley's system of magic and its emphasis on human will.[119]Given the importance of the Will to Schopenhauer's overarching system, this amounts to "suggesting his whole philosophical system had magical powers."[120]Schopenhauer rejected the theory ofdisenchantmentand claimed philosophy should synthesize itself with magic, which he believed amount to "practical metaphysics".[121]

Neoplatonism,including the traditions ofPlotinusand to a lesser extentMarsilio Ficino,has also been cited as an influence on Schopenhauer.[122]

Interests[edit]

Schopenhauer had a wide range of interests, from science and opera to occultism and literature.

In his student years, Schopenhauer went more often to lectures in the sciences than philosophy. He kept a strong interest as his personal library contained near to 200 books of scientific literature at his death, and his works refer to scientific titles not found in the library.[16]: 170 

Many evenings were spent in the theatre, opera and ballet; Schopenhauer especially liked the operas ofMozart,RossiniandBellini.[123]Schopenhauer considered music the highest art, and played the flute during his whole life.[16]: 30 

As a polyglot, he knew German, Italian, Spanish, French, English,Latinandancient Greek,and was an avid reader of poetry and literature. He particularly reveredGoethe,Petrarch,CalderónandShakespeare.

If Goethe had not been sent into the world simultaneously with Kant in order to counterbalance him, so to speak, in the spirit of the age, the latter would have been haunted like a nightmare many an aspiring mind and would have oppressed it with great affliction. But now the two have an infinitely wholesome effect from opposite directions and will probably raise the German spirit to a height surpassing even that of antiquity.[16]: 240 

In philosophy, his most important influences were, according to himself, Kant,Platoand theUpanishads.Concerning the Upanishads andVedas,he writes inThe World as Will and Representation:

If the reader has also received the benefit of the Vedas, the access to which by means of the Upanishads is in my eyes the greatest privilege which this still young century (1818) may claim before all previous centuries, if then the reader, I say, has received his initiation in primeval Indian wisdom, and received it with an open heart, he will be prepared in the very best way for hearing what I have to tell him. It will not sound to him strange, as to many others, much less disagreeable; for I might, if it did not sound conceited, contend that every one of the detached statements which constitute the Upanishads, may be deduced as a necessary result from the fundamental thoughts which I have to enunciate, though those deductions themselves are by no means to be found there.[124]

Thoughts on other philosophers[edit]

Giordano Bruno and Spinoza[edit]

Schopenhauer sawBrunoandSpinozaas philosophers not bound to their age or nation. "Both were fulfilled by the thought, that as manifold the appearances of the world may be, it is stillonebeing, that appears in all of them.... Consequently, there is no place for God as creator of the world in their philosophy, but God is the world itself. "[125][126]

Schopenhauer expressed regret that Spinoza stuck, for the presentation of his philosophy, with the concepts ofscholasticismandCartesian philosophy,and tried to use geometrical proofs that do not hold because of vague and overly broad definitions. Bruno on the other hand, who knew much about nature and ancient literature, presented his ideas with Italian vividness, and is amongst philosophers the only one who comes near Plato's poetic and dramatic power of exposition.[125][126]

Schopenhauer noted that their philosophies do not provide any ethics, and it is therefore very remarkable that Spinoza called his main workEthics.In fact, it could be considered complete from the standpoint of life-affirmation, if one completely ignores morality and self-denial.[127]It is yet even more remarkable that Schopenhauer mentions Spinoza as an example of the denial of the will, if one uses the French biography by Jean Maximilien Lucas[128]as the key toTractatus de Intellectus Emendatione.[129]

Immanuel Kant[edit]

Schopenhauer's philosophy took Kant's work as its foundation. While he praised Kant's greatness, he nonetheless included a highly detailed criticism of Kantian philosophy as an appendix toThe World as Will and Representation.

The importance of Kant for Schopenhauer, in philosophy as well as on a personal level, cannot be overstated. Kant's philosophy was the foundation of Schopenhauer's, and he had high praise for theTranscendental Aestheticsection of Kant'sCritique of Pure Reason.Schopenhauer maintained that Kant stands in the same relation to philosophers such as Berkeley andPlato,as Copernicus toHicetas,Philolaus,andAristarchus:Kant succeeded in demonstrating what previous philosophers merely asserted.

Schopenhauer writes about Kant's influence on his work in the preface to the second edition ofThe World as Will and Representation:

I have already explained in the preface to the first edition, that my philosophy is founded on that of Kant, and therefore presupposes a thorough knowledge of it. I repeat this here. For Kant's teaching produces in the mind of everyone who has comprehended it a fundamental change which is so great that it may be regarded as an intellectual new-birth. It alone is able really to remove the inborn realism which proceeds from the original character of the intellect, which neitherBerkeleynorMalebranchesucceed in doing, for they remain too much in the universal, while Kant goes into the particular, and indeed in a way that is quite unexampled both before and after him, and which has quite a peculiar, and, we might say, immediate effect upon the mind in consequence of which it undergoes a complete undeception, and forthwith looks at all things in another light. Only in this way can any one become susceptible to the more positive expositions which I have to give. On the other hand, he who has not mastered the Kantian philosophy, whatever else he may have studied, is, as it were, in a state of innocence; that is to say, he remains in the grasp of that natural and childish realism in which we are all born, and which fits us for everything possible, with the single exception of philosophy.[130]

In his study room, one bust was ofBuddha,the other was of Kant.[131]The bond which Schopenhauer felt with the philosopher of Königsberg is demonstrated in an unfinished poem he dedicated to Kant (included in volume 2 of theParerga):

With my eyes I followed thee into the blue sky,
And there thy flight dissolved from view.
Alone I stayed in the crowd below,
Thy word and thy book my only solace.—
Through the strains of thy inspiring words
I sought to dispel the dreary solitude.
Strangers on all sides surround me.
The world is desolate and life interminable.[132]

Schopenhauer dedicated one fifth of his main work,The World as Will and Representation,to a detailedcriticism of the Kantian philosophy.

Schopenhauer praised Kant for his distinction between appearance and thething-in-itself,whereas the general consensus inGerman idealismwas that this was the weakest spot of Kant's theory,[42]since, according to Kant, causality can find application on objects of experience only, and consequently, things-in-themselves cannot be the cause of appearances. The inadmissibility of this reasoning was also acknowledged by Schopenhauer. He insisted that this was a true conclusion, drawn from false premises.[133]

Post-Kantian school[edit]

The leading figures ofpost-Kantian philosophyJohann Gottlieb Fichte,F. W. J. SchellingandG. W. F. Hegel—were not respected by Schopenhauer. He argued that they were not philosophers at all, for they lacked "the first requirement of a philosopher, namely a seriousness and honesty of inquiry."[134]Rather, they were merely sophists who, excelling in the art of beguiling the public, pursued their own selfish interests (such as professional advancement within the university system). Diatribes against the alleged vacuity, dishonesty, pomposity, and self-interest of these contemporaries are to be found throughout Schopenhauer's published writings. The following passage is an example:

All this explains the painful impression with which we are seized when, after studying genuine thinkers, we come to the writings of Fichte and Schelling, or even to the presumptuously scribbled nonsense of Hegel, produced as it was with a boundless, though justified, confidence in German stupidity. With those genuine thinkers one always found anhonestinvestigation of truth and just ashonestan attempt to communicate their ideas to others. Therefore whoever reads Kant, Locke, Hume, Malebranche, Spinoza, and Descartes feels elevated and agreeably impressed. This is produced through communion with a noble mind which has and awakens ideas and which thinks and sets one thinking. The reverse of all this takes place when we read the above-mentioned three German sophists. An unbiased reader, opening one of their books and then asking himself whether this is the tone of a thinker wanting to instruct or that of a charlatan wanting to impress, cannot be five minutes in any doubt; here everything breathes so much ofdishonesty.[135]

Schopenhauer deemed Schelling the most talented of the three and wrote that he would recommend his "elucidatory paraphrase of the highly important doctrine of Kant" concerning the intelligible character, if he had been honest enough to admit he was parroting Kant, instead of hiding this relation in a cunning manner.[136]

Schopenhauer reserved his most unqualified damning condemnation for Hegel, whom he considered less worthy than Fichte or Schelling. Whereas Fichte was merely a windbag (Windbeutel), Hegel was a "commonplace, inane, loathsome, repulsive, and ignorant charlatan."[137]The philosophersKarl PopperandMario Bungeagreed with this distinction.[138][139]Hegel, Schopenhauer wrote in the preface to hisTwo Fundamental Problems of Ethics,not only "performed no service to philosophy, but he has had a detrimental influence on philosophy, and thereby on German literature in general, really a downright stupefying, or we could even say a pestilential influence, which it is therefore the duty of everyone capable of thinking for himself and judging for himself to counteract in the most express terms at every opportunity."[140]

Influence and legacy[edit]

Sculpture of SchopenhauerbyElisabeth Ney

Schopenhauer remained the most influential German philosopher until theFirst World War.[141]His philosophy was a starting point for a new generation of philosophers includingJulius Bahnsen,Paul Deussen,Lazar von Hellenbach,Karl Robert Eduard von Hartmann,Ernst Otto Lindner,Philipp Mainländer,Friedrich Nietzsche,Olga PlümacherandAgnes Taubert.His legacy shaped the intellectual debate, and forced movements that were utterly opposed to him,neo-Kantianismandpositivism,to address issues they would otherwise have completely ignored, and in doing so he changed them markedly.[141]The French writerMaupassantcommented that "to-day even those who execrate him seem to carry in their own souls particles of his thought".[142]Other philosophers of the 19th century who cited his influence includeHans Vaihinger,Volkelt,SolovyovandWeininger.

Schopenhauer was well read by physicists, most notablyEinstein,Schrödinger,Wolfgang Pauli,[143]andMajorana.[144]Einstein described Schopenhauer's thoughts as a "continual consolation" and called him a genius.[145]In his Berlin study three figures hung on the wall:Faraday,Maxwell,Schopenhauer.[146]Konrad Wachsmannrecalled: "He often sat with one of the well-worn Schopenhauer volumes, and as he sat there, he seemed so pleased, as if he were engaged with a serene and cheerful work."[147]

WhenErwin Schrödingerdiscovered Schopenhauer ( "the greatest savant of the West" ) he considered switching his study of physics to philosophy.[148]He maintained the idealistic views during the rest of his life.[149]Wolfgang Pauliaccepted the main tenet of Schopenhauer's metaphysics, that thething-in-itselfis will.[150]

But most of all Schopenhauer is famous for his influence on artists.Richard Wagnerbecame one of the earliest and most famous adherents of the Schopenhauerian philosophy.[151]The admiration was not mutual, and Schopenhauer proclaimed: "I remain faithful to Rossini and Mozart!"[152]So he has beennicknamed"the artist's philosopher".[1]See alsoInfluence of Schopenhauer onTristan und Isolde.

Schopenhauer depicted on a 500 million Danzig papiermark note (1923)
Schopenhauer depicted on a 500 million Danzigpapiermarknote (1923)

Under the influence of Schopenhauer,Leo Tolstoybecame convinced that the truth of all religions lies in self-renunciation. When he read Schopenhauer's philosophy, Tolstoy exclaimed "at present I am convinced that Schopenhauer is the greatest genius among men.... It is the whole world in an incomparably beautiful and clear reflection."[153]He said that what he has written inWar and Peaceis also said by Schopenhauer inThe World as Will and Representation.[154]

Jorge Luis Borgesremarked that the reason he had never attempted to write a systematic account of his world view, despite his penchant for philosophy and metaphysics in particular, was because Schopenhauer had already written it for him.[155]

Other figures in literature who were strongly influenced by Schopenhauer wereThomas Mann,Thomas Hardy,Afanasy Fet,J.-K. HuysmansandGeorge Santayana.[156]In Herman Melville's final years, while he wroteBilly Budd,he read Schopenhauer's essays and marked them heavily. Scholar Brian Yothers notes that Melville "marked numerous misanthropic and even suicidal remarks, suggesting an attraction to the most extreme sorts of solitude, but he also made note of Schopenhauer's reflection on the moral ambiguities of genius."[157]Schopenhauer's attraction to and discussions of both Eastern and Western religions in conjunction with each other made an impression on Melville in his final years.

Sergei Prokofiev,although initially reluctant to engage with works noted for their pessimism, became fascinated with Schopenhauer after readingAphorisms on the Wisdom of LifeinParerga and Paralipomena."With his truths Schopenhauer gave me a spiritual world and an awareness of happiness."[158]

Friedrich Nietzscheowed the awakening of his philosophical interest to readingThe World as Will and Representationand admitted that he was one of the few philosophers that he respected, dedicating to him his essay "Schopenhauer als Erzieher",[159]one of hisUntimely Meditations.

Commemorative stamp of the Deutsche Bundespost

Early in his career,Ludwig Wittgensteinadopted Schopenhauer's epistemological idealism, and some traits of Schopenhauer's influence (particularly Schopenhauerian transcendentalism) can be observed in theTractatus Logico-Philosophicus.[160][161]Later on, Wittgenstein rejected epistemologicaltranscendental idealismforGottlob Frege's conceptualrealism.In later years, Wittgenstein became highly dismissive of Schopenhauer, describing him as an ultimately shallow thinker.[162][163]His friendBertrand Russellhad a low opinion on the philosopher, and even came to attack him in hisHistory of Western Philosophyfor hypocritically praising asceticism yet not acting upon it.[164]

Opposite to Russell on the foundations of mathematics, the Dutch mathematicianL. E. J. Brouwerincorporated Kant's and Schopenhauer's ideas in the philosophical school ofintuitionism,where mathematics is considered as a purely mental activity instead of an analytic activity wherein objective properties of reality are revealed. Brouwer was also influenced by Schopenhauer's metaphysics, and wrote an essay on mysticism.

Schopenhauer's philosophy has made its way into a novel,The Schopenhauer Cure,by American existential psychiatrist and emeritus professor of psychiatryIrvin Yalom.

Schopenhauer's philosophy, and the discussions onphilosophical pessimismit has engendered, has been the focus of contemporary thinkers such asDavid Benatar,Thomas Ligotti,andEugene Thacker.Their work also served as an inspiration for the popular HBO TV seriesTrue Detectiveas well asLife Is Beautiful.[165]In this regard, Schopenhauer is sometimes considered the founding father of today'santinatalism.[166]

Selected bibliography[edit]

  • On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason(Ueber die vierfache Wurzel des Satzes vom zureichenden Grunde), 1813
  • On Vision and Colors(Ueber das Sehn und die Farben), 1816ISBN978-0-85496-988-3
  • Theory of Colors(Theoria colorum physiologica), 1830.
  • The World as Will and Representation(alternatively translated asThe World as Will and Idea;original German isDie Welt als Wille und Vorstellung): vol. 1, 1818–1819, vol. 2, 1844
  • The Art of Being Right(Eristische Dialektik: Die Kunst, Recht zu Behalten), 1831
  • On the Will in Nature(Ueber den Willen in der Natur), 1836ISBN978-0-85496-999-9
  • On the Freedom of the Will(Ueber die Freiheit des menschlichen Willens), 1838ISBN978-0-631-14552-3
  • On the Basis of Morality(Ueber die Grundlage der Moral), 1839
  • Schopenhauer, Arthur(2010).The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics.Translated by Cartwright, David E.; Erdmann, Edward E. London:Oxford University Press.ISBN9780199297221.ContainsOn the Freedom of the WillandOn the Basis of Morality.
  • Schopenhauer, Arthur(September 1840) [Stated date: 1841.].Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik, behandelt in zwei akademischen Preisschriften(in German). Frankfurt am Main: Johann Christian Hermannsche Buchandlung.Retrieved15 April2024.FreelyavailablefromInternet Archive.ContainsPreisschrift über die Freiheit des WillensandPreisschrift über die Grundlage der Moral.
  • Parerga and Paralipomena(2 vols., 1851) – Reprint: (Oxford: Clarendon Press) (2 vols., 1974) (English translation by E. F. J. Payne[167])
  • An Enquiry concerning Ghost-seeing, and what is connected therewith (Versuch über das Geistersehn und was damit zusammenhangt),1851
  • Arthur Schopenhauer,Manuscript Remains,Volume II, Berg Publishers Ltd.,ISBN978-0-85496-539-7

Online[edit]

See also[edit]

References[edit]

  1. ^ab"Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860) (Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy)".
  2. ^Frederick C. Beiserreviews the commonly held position that Schopenhauer was a transcendental idealist and he rejects it: "Though it is deeply heretical from the standpoint of transcendental idealism, Schopenhauer's objective standpoint involves a form oftranscendental realism,i.e. the assumption of the independent reality of the world of experience. "(Beiser 2016, p. 40)
  3. ^abVoluntarism (philosophy)Britannica
  4. ^Arthur Schopenhauer,Arthur Schopenhauer: The World as Will and Presentation, Volume 1,Routledge, 2016, p. 211: "the world [is a] merepresentation,object for a subject... "
  5. ^Lennart Svensson,Borderline: A Traditionalist Outlook for Modern Man,Numen Books, 2015, p. 71: "[Schopenhauer] said that 'the world is our conception'. A world without a perceiver would in that case be an impossibility. But we can—he said—gain knowledge about Essential Reality for looking into ourselves, by introspection.... This is one of many examples of the anthropic principle. The world is there for the sake of man."
  6. ^abStephen Puryear,"Schopenhauer on the Rights of Animals."European Journal of Philosophy25/2 (2017):250–269.
  7. ^abThe World as Will and Representation,vol. 3, Ch. 50.
  8. ^abDale Jacquette, ed. (2007).Schopenhauer, Philosophy and the Arts.Cambridge University Press. p. 162.ISBN978-0-521-04406-6.For Kant, the mathematical sublime, as seen for example in the starry heavens, suggests to imagination the infinite, which in turn leads by subtle turns of contemplation to the concept of God. Schopenhauer's atheism will have none of this, and he rightly observes that despite adopting Kant's distinction between the dynamical and mathematical sublime, his theory of the sublime, making reference to the struggles and sufferings of struggles and sufferings of Will, is unlike Kant's.
  9. ^Wells, John C. (2008),Longman Pronunciation Dictionary(3rd ed.), Longman,ISBN978-1-4058-8118-0
  10. ^Arthur Schopenhauer (2004).Essays and Aphorisms.Penguin Classics. p.23.ISBN978-0-14-044227-4.
  11. ^Magee, Bryan (14 August 1997)."The World as Will".The Philosophy of Schopenhauer(1 ed.). Oxford University PressOxford. pp. 137–163.doi:10.1093/0198237227.003.0007.ISBN978-0-19-823722-8.
  12. ^Vandenabeele, Bart (December 2007)."Schopenhauer on the Values of Aesthetic Experience".The Southern Journal of Philosophy.45(4): 565–582.doi:10.1111/j.2041-6962.2007.tb00065.x.
  13. ^See the book-length study about oriental influences on the genesis of Schopenhauer's philosophy byUrs App:Schopenhauer's Compass. An Introduction to Schopenhauer's Philosophy and its Origins.Wil: UniversityMedia, 2014 (ISBN978-3-906000-03-9)
    • Hergenhahn, B. R. (2009).An Introduction to the History of Psychology(6th ed.). Cengage Learning. p. 216.ISBN978-0-495-50621-8.Although Schopenhauer was an atheist, he realized that his philosophy of denial had been part of several great religions; for example, Christianity, Hinduism, and Buddhism.
  14. ^Arthur Schopenhauer (2004).Essays and Aphorisms.Penguin Classics. pp.22–36.ISBN978-0-14-044227-4....but there has been none who tried with so great a show of learning to demonstrate that the pessimistic outlook isjustified,that life itself is really bad. It is to this end that Schopenhauer's metaphysic of will and idea exists.
    • Studies in Pessimism– audiobook fromLibriVox.
    • David A. Leeming; Kathryn Madden; Stanton Marlan, eds. (2009).Encyclopedia of Psychology and Religion, Volume 2.Springer. p. 824.ISBN978-0-387-71801-9.A more accurate statement might be that for a German—rather than a French or British writer of that time—Schopenhauer was an honest and open atheist.
  15. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur; Günter Zöller; Eric F. J. Payne (1999).Chronology.Prize Essay on the Freedom of the Will.Cambridge University Press.p. xxx.ISBN978-0-521-57766-3.
  16. ^abcdefghijklmnopqrstuvwxyzaaabacadaeafagahaiajakalamanaoapaqarasatauavawaxayazbabbbcbdbebfbgbhbibjbkblbmbnbobpbqbrbsbtbubvbwbxbybzcacbcccdcecfcgchcicjckclcmcncocpcqcrcsctcucvcwcxcyczdadbdcdddedfdgdhdidjdkdldmdndodpdqdrdsdtdudvdwdxdyCartwright, David E. (2010).Schopenhauer: A Biography.Cambridge University Press.ISBN978-0-521-82598-6.
  17. ^Bullock, A.B. (1920).The Supreme Human Tragedy: And Other Essays.C.W. Daniel. p. 53.Retrieved22 October2022.
  18. ^Safranski (1990), p. 12
  19. ^Wallace, W. (2003).Life of Arthur Schopenhauer.Honolulu: University Press of the Pacific. p. 59.ISBN978-1-4102-0641-1.
  20. ^Durant, Will,The Story of Philosophy,Garden City Publishing Co., Inc., New York, p. 350
  21. ^"Schopenhauer: A Pessimist in the Optimistic Month of May".Germanic American Institute. Archived fromthe originalon 11 June 2010.Retrieved12 March2010.
  22. ^"Full text of" Selected Essays Of Schopenhauer "".Retrieved12 March2010.
  23. ^abFredriksson, Einar H. (2001), "The Dutch Publishing Scene: Elsevier and North-Holland",A Century of Science Publishing: A Collection of Essays,Amsterdam: IOS Press, pp. 61–76,ISBN978-4-274-90424-0
  24. ^Willson, A. Leslie (1961). "Friedrich Majer: Romantic Indologist".Texas Studies in Literature and Language.3(1): 40–49.ISSN0040-4691.JSTOR40753707.
  25. ^abcClarke 1997,pp. 67–68.
  26. ^Clarke 1997,pp. 67–69.
  27. ^Clarke 1997,pp. 273.
  28. ^Clarke 1997,p. 69.
  29. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur (22 April 2019).The world as will and idea.Classic Wisdom Reprint.ISBN978-1-950330-23-2.OCLC1229105608.
  30. ^Although the first volume was published by December 1818, it was printed with a title page erroneously giving the year as 1819 (seeBraunschweig, Yael (2013), "Schopenhauer and Rossinian Universiality: On the Italianate in Schopenhauer's Metaphysics of Music",The Invention of Beethoven and Rossini: Historiography, Analysis, Criticism,Cambridge:Cambridge University Press, p.297, n. 7,ISBN978-0-521-76805-4).
  31. ^Safranski, Rüdiger (1991)Schopenhauer and the Wild Years of Philosophy.Harvard University Press. p. 244
  32. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur. Author's preface to "On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of sufficient reason", p. 1 (On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reasonon Wikisource.)
  33. ^Schopenhauer 2010,pp. xxviii, xxxix
  34. ^Dale Jacquette,The Philosophy of Schopenhauer,Routledge, 2015: "Biographical sketch".
  35. ^Schopenhauer: his life and philosophyby H. Zimmern – 1932 – G. Allen & Unwin.
  36. ^Lewis, Peter (15 February 2013).Arthur Schopenhauer, 2013.Reaktion Books.ISBN978-1-78023-069-6.
  37. ^Letter to Goethe on 23 January 1816: "Ich weiß, daß durch mich die Wahrheit geredet hat, – in dieser kleinen Sache, wie dereinst in größern."
  38. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur.The World as Will and Representation.Vol. 1. Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy.But the whole teaching of Kant contains really nothing more about this than the oft-repeated meaningless expression: 'The empirical element in perception is given from without.'... always through the same meaningless metaphorical expression: 'The empirical perception is given us.'
  39. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur.On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason.§ 21.For sensation is and remains a process within the organism and is limited, as such, to the region within the skin; it cannot therefore contain any thing which lies beyond that region, or, in other words, anything that is outside us.... It is only when the Understanding begins to apply its sole form, the causal law, that a powerful transformation takes place, by which subjective sensation becomes objective perception.
  40. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur.On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason.§ 21.
  41. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur.The World as Will and Representation.Vol. 1, § 4.The contrary doctrine that the law of causality results from experience, which was the scepticism of Hume, is first refuted by this. For the independence of the knowledge of causality of all experience,—that is, its a priori character—can only be deduced from the dependence of all experience upon it; and this deduction can only be accomplished by proving, in the manner here indicated, and explained in the passages referred to above, that the knowledge of causality is included in perception in general, to which all experience belongs, and therefore in respect of experience is completely a priori, does not presuppose it, but is presupposed by it as a condition.
  42. ^abDavid E. Cartwright; Edward E. Erdmann.Introduction to "On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason".Cambridge University Press. pp. xvi–xvii.He had also rehearsed for the first time his physiological arguments for the intellectual nature of intuition [Anschauung, objective perception] in his "On Vision and Colours", and he had discussed how his philosophy was corroborated by the sciences in "On Will in Nature".... Like the German Idealists, Schopenhauer was convinced that Kant's great unknown, the thing in itself, is the weak point of the critical philosophy.
  43. ^Kant, Immanuel.Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics.Translated by Paul Carus. § 52c.
  44. ^See the quotation of Schopenhauer inStorm, Jason Josephson (2021).Metamodernism: The Future of Theory.Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 36–37.ISBN978-0-226-78665-0.
  45. ^Young, Julian (2005).Schopenhauer(1 ed.). Routledge. pp. 4–25.doi:10.4324/9780203022108.ISBN978-1-134-32883-3.
  46. ^Einstein, Albert (1935).The World as I See It,p. 14. Snowball Publishing.ISBN1-4948-7706-6.
  47. ^The World as Will and Representation, Vol. 1,§68
  48. ^The World as Will and Representation,Vol. 1, §38
  49. ^The World as Will and Representation,Vol. 1, §34
  50. ^Daniel Albright,Modernism and Music,2004, p. 39, footnote 34
  51. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur (1970).Essays and Aphorisms.Penguin Classics. p.162.ISBN978-0-14-044227-4.
  52. ^abThe World as Will and Representation,vol. 2, ch. 13
  53. ^"I wanted in this way to stress and demonstrate the great difference, indeed opposition, between knowledge of perception and abstract or reflected knowledge. Hitherto this difference has received too little attention, and its establishment is a fundamental feature of my philosophy..." –The World as Will and Representation.,vol. 2, ch. 7, p. 88 (trans. Payne)
  54. ^This comment by Schopenhauer was called "an acute observation" bySir Thomas L. Heath.In his translation ofThe Elements,vol. 1, Book I, "Note on Common Notion 4", Heath made this judgment and also noted that Schopenhauer's remark "was a criticism in advance ofHelmholtz'theory ". Helmholtz had" maintained that geometry requires us to assume the actual existence of rigid bodies and their free mobility in space "and is therefore" dependent on mechanics ".
  55. ^What Schopenhauer calls the eighth axiom is Euclid's Common Notion 4.
  56. ^"Motion of anobjectin space does not belong in a pure science, and consequently not in geometry. For the fact that something is movable cannot be cognizeda priori,but can be cognized only through experience. "(Kant,Critique of Pure Reason,B 155, Note)
  57. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur.The World as Will and Representation.Vol. 1, § 53.
  58. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur.The World as Will and Representation.Vol. 1, § 23.
  59. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur.The World as Will and Representation.Vol. 1, § 66.
  60. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur.On the Basis of Morality.§ 19.
  61. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur.Parerga and Paralipomena.Vol. 2, § 173.
  62. ^abcThe World as Will and IdeaVol. 1 § 63
  63. ^abcSchopenhauer, Arthur.The World as Will and Representation.Vol. 1, § 68.
  64. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur.The World as Will and Representation: Supplements to the Fourth Book
  65. ^The Oxford Encyclopedic English Dictionary.Schopenhauer: Oxford University Press. 1991. p. 1298.ISBN978-0-19-861248-3.
  66. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur,The World as Will and Representation,Supplements to the Fourth Book
  67. ^Darwin, Charles.The Descent of Man.p. 586.
  68. ^"Nearly a century before Freud... in Schopenhauer there is, for the first time, an explicit philosophy of the unconscious and of the body." Safranski p. 345.
  69. ^The World as Will and Representation,Vol. 2, Ch. 47
  70. ^abParerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 2,"On Jurisprudence and Politics," §127, trans. Payne (p. 254).
  71. ^Parerga and Paralipomena, Vol. 2,"On Jurisprudence and Politics," §127, trans. Payne (p. 255).
  72. ^The World as Will and Representation,Vol. 2, Ch. 12
  73. ^Schopenhauer,The World as Will and Representation,Vol. I, § 62.
  74. ^"... he who attempts to punish in accordance with reason does not retaliate on account of the past wrong (for he could not undo something which has been done) but for the future, so that neither the wrongdoer himself, nor others who see him being punished, will do wrong again." Plato, "Protagoras",324 B. Plato wrote that punishment should" be an example to other men not to offend ". Plato,"Laws",Book IX, 863.
  75. ^Parerga and Paralipomena,Vol. 2, "On Philosophy and Natural Science," §92, trans. Payne (p. 158-159).
  76. ^Parerga and Paralipomena,Vol. 2, "On Ethics," §114, trans. Payne (p. 212).
  77. ^"Fragments for the History of Philosophy",Parerga and Paralipomena,Volume I, trans. Payne (p. 126).
  78. ^"Arthur Schopenhauer: Ueber die Weiber".aboq.org.
  79. ^Rodgers(environmentalist) andThompsoninPhilosophers Behaving Badlycall Schopenhauer "a misogynist without rival in... Western philosophy".
  80. ^Feminism and the Limits of Equality PA Cain – Ga. L. Rev., 1989
  81. ^Julian Young (23 June 2005).Schopenhauer.Psychology Press. p. 242.ISBN978-0-415-33346-7.
  82. ^Long, Sandra Salser (Spring 1984). "Arthur Schopenhauer and Elisabet Ney".Southwest Review.69(2): 130–47.JSTOR43469632.
  83. ^Safranski (1990), Chapter 24. p. 348.
  84. ^Schopenhauer 1969,p. 566
  85. ^Schopenhauer 1969,p. 567
  86. ^Payne,The World as Will and Representation,Vol. II, p. 519
  87. ^On the Suffering of the World(1970), p. 35. Penguin Books – Great Ideas.
  88. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur (1969). E. F. J. Payne (ed.).The World as Will and Representation.Vol. II. New York: Dover Publications. p. 527.ISBN978-0-486-21762-8.
  89. ^Essays and Aphorisms,trans. R.J. Hollingdale, Middlesex: London, 1970, p. 154
  90. ^Nietzsche and Modern German Thoughtby K. Ansell-Pearson – 1991 – Psychology Press.
  91. ^Christina Gerhardt, "Thinking With: Animals in Schopenhauer, Horkheimer and Adorno."Critical Theory and Animals.Ed. John Sanbonmatsu. Lanham: Rowland, 2011. 137–157.
  92. ^"Unlike the intellect, it [the Will] does not depend on the perfection of the organism, but is essentially the same in all animals as what is known to us so intimately. Accordingly, the animal has all the emotions of humans, such as joy, grief, fear, anger, love, hatred, strong desire, envy, and so on. The great difference between human and animal rests solely on the intellect's degrees of perfection.On the Will in Nature,"Physiology and Pathology".
  93. ^Quoted inSchopenhauer, Arthur (1994).Philosophical Writings.London: Continuum. p. 233.ISBN978-0-8264-0729-0.
  94. ^Quoted inRyder, Richard (2000).Animal Revolution: Changing Attitudes Towards Speciesism.Oxford: Berg Publishers. p. 57.ISBN978-1-85973-330-1.
  95. ^"... in English all animals are of the neuter gender and so are represented by the pronoun 'it,' just as if they were inanimate things. The effect of this artifice is quite revolting, especially in the case of primates, such as dogs, monkeys, and the like...."On the Basis of Morality,§ 19.
  96. ^"I recall having read of an Englishman who, while hunting in India, had shot a monkey; he could not forget the look which the dying animal gave him, and since then had never again fired at monkeys."On the Basis of Morality,§ 19.
  97. ^"[Sir William Harris] describes how he shot his first elephant, a female. The next morning he went to look for the dead animal; all the other elephants had fled from the neighborhood except a young one, who had spent the night with its dead mother. Forgetting all fear, he came toward the sportsmen with the clearest and liveliest evidence of inconsolable grief, and put his tiny trunk round them in order to appeal to them for help. Harris says he was then filled with real remorse for what he had done, and felt as if he had committed a murder."On the basis of morality,§ 19.
  98. ^"His contempt for animals, who, as mere things for our use, are declared by him to be without rights,... in conjunction with Pantheism, is at the same time absurd and abominable."The World as Will and Representation,Vol. 2, Chapter 50.
  99. ^Spinoza,Ethics,Pt. IV, Prop. XXXVII, Note I.: "Still I do not deny that beasts feel: what I deny is, that we may not consult our own advantage and use them as we please, treating them in a way which best suits us; for their nature is not like ours..." This is the exact opposite of Schopenhauer's doctrine. Also,Ethics,Appendix, 26, "whatsoever there be in nature beside man, a regard for our advantage does not call on us to preserve, but to preserve or destroy according to its various capacities, and to adapt to our use as best we may."
  100. ^"Such are the matters which I engage to prove in Prop. xviii of this Part, whereby it is plain that the law against the slaughtering of animals is founded rather on vain superstition and womanish pity than on sound reason. The rational quest of what is useful to us further teaches us the necessity of associating ourselves with our fellow-men, but not with beasts, or things, whose nature is different from our own; we have the same rights in respect to them as they have in respect to us. Nay, as everyone's right is defined by his virtue, or power, men have far greater rights over beasts than beasts have over men. Still I affirm that beasts feel. But I also affirm that we may consult our own advantage and use them as we please, treating them in the way which best suits us; for their nature is not like ours, and their emotions are naturally different from human emotions."Ethics,Part 4, Prop. 37, Note 1.
  101. ^Quoted inMadigan, Tim."Schopenhauer's Compassionate Morality | Issue 52 | Philosophy Now".Philosophy Now.Retrieved16 September2023.
  102. ^abcdClarke 1997,p. 68.
  103. ^Christopher McCoy, 3–4
  104. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur (1840)."Part IV".On the Basis of Morality.Translated by Bullock, Arthur Brodrick. London:Swan Sonnenschein(published 1908). pp. 269–271 – viaInternet Archive.
  105. ^Dutt, Purohit Bhagavan."Western Indologists: A Study in Motives".Archived fromthe originalon 2 August 2010.Retrieved9 May2009.
  106. ^Christopher McCoy, 54–56
  107. ^Abelson, Peter (April 1993). Schopenhauer and BuddhismArchived28 June 2011 at theWayback Machine.Philosophy East and WestVolume 43, Number 2, pp. 255–278. University of Hawaii Press. Retrieved on: 12 April 2008.
  108. ^Janaway,Christopher,Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy,pp. 28 ff.
  109. ^David Burton, "Buddhism, Knowledge and Liberation: A Philosophical Study." Ashgate Publishing, Ltd., 2004, p. 22.
  110. ^John J. Holder,Early Buddhist Discourses.Hackett Publishing Company, 2006, p. xx.
  111. ^ "Schopenhauer is often said to be the first modern Western philosopher to attempt integration of his work with Eastern ways of thinking. That he was the first is true, but the claim that he wasinfluencedby Indian thought needs qualification. There is a remarkable correspondence in broad terms between some central Schopenhauerian doctrines and Buddhism: notably in the views that empirical existence is suffering, that suffering originates in desires, and that salvation can be attained by the extinction of desires. These three 'truths of the Buddha' are mirrored closely in the essential structure of the doctrine of the will. "(On this, see Dorothea W. Dauer,Schopenhauer as Transmitter of Buddhist Ideas.Note also the discussion by Bryan Magee,The Philosophy of Schopenhauer,pp. 14–15, 316–321). Janaway, Christopher,Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy,p. 28 f.
  112. ^The World as Will and Representation,Vol. 2, Ch. 17
  113. ^Artistic detachment in Japan and the West: psychic distance in comparative aestheticsby S. Odin – 2001 – University of Hawaii Press.
  114. ^Parerga & Paralipomena,vol. I, p. 106., trans. E.F.J. Payne.
  115. ^World as Will and Representation,vol. I, p. 273, trans. E.F.J. Payne.
  116. ^Christopher McCoy, 3
  117. ^App, UrsArthur Schopenhauer and China.Sino-Platonic PapersNr. 200 (April 2010)(PDF, 8.7 Mb PDF, 164 p.; Schopenhauer's early notes on Buddhism reproduced in Appendix). This study provides an overview of the actual discovery of Buddhism by Schopenhauer.
  118. ^Hutton, KennethCompassion in Schopenhauer and Śāntideva.Journal of Buddhist EthicsVol. 21 (2014)
  119. ^abJosephson-Storm, Jason (2017).The Myth of Disenchantment: Magic, Modernity, and the Birth of the Human Sciences.Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 187–188.ISBN978-0-226-40336-6.
  120. ^Quote from Josephson-Storm (2017), p. 188.
  121. ^Josephson-Storm (2017), pp. 188–189.
  122. ^Anderson, Mark (2009). "Experimental Subversions of Modernity".Pure: Modernity, Philosophy, and the One.Sophia Perennis.ISBN978-1-59731-094-9.
  123. ^Carnegy, Patrick.Wagner and the Art of the Theatre.p. 51.
  124. ^The World as Will and RepresentationPreface to the first edition, p. xiii
  125. ^abSchopenhauer, Arthur.The World as Will and Representation.Vol. 1, Criticism of the Kantian Philosophy. Note 5.
  126. ^ab"Handschriftlicher, Nachlass, Vorlesungen und Abhandlungen".Gutenberg Spiegel.
  127. ^Abschnitt: Handschriftlicher Nachlaß.§ 588.Es kann daher eine vollkommen wahre Philosophie geben, die ganz von der Verneinung des Lebens abstrahirt, diese ganz ignorirt.
  128. ^"Vie de Spinoza – Wikisource".fr.wikisource.org.
  129. ^The World as Will and Representation.§ 68.We might to a certain extent regard the well-known French biography of Spinoza as a case in point, if we used as a key to it that noble introduction to his very insufficient essay, "De Emendatione Intellects", a passage which I can also recommend as the most effectual means I know of stilling the storm of the passions.
  130. ^Arthur Schopenhauer.World as Will and Representation.Vol. 1, Preface of the Second Edition.
  131. ^Jerauld McGill, Vivian (1931).Schopenhauer. Pessimist and Pagan.p. 320.
  132. ^Parerga and Paralipomena: Short Philosophical Essays, Volume 2,trans. Payne, p. 655–656.
  133. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur.The World as Will and Representation.Vol. 1 Criticism of the Kantian philosophy. Translated by J. Kemp.With the proof of the thing in itself it has happened to Kant precisely as with that of the a priori nature of the law of causality. Both doctrines are true, but their proof is false. They thus belong to the class of true conclusions from false premises.
  134. ^Parerga and Paralipomena,Vol. 1, Appendix to "Sketch of a History of the Doctrine of the Ideal and the Real," trans. E. J. Payne (Oxford, 1974), p. 21.
  135. ^Parerga and Paralipomena,Vol. 1, Appendix to "Sketch of a History of the Doctrine of the Ideal and the Real," trans. E. J. Payne (Oxford, 1974), p. 23.
  136. ^Schopenhauer, Arthur.On the Freedom of the Will.p. 82.
  137. ^Parerga and Paralipomena,Vol. I, "Fragments for the History of Philosophy", Sec. 13, trans. E. J. Payne (Oxford, 1974), p. 96.
  138. ^Popper, Karl (1946). "The Open Society and Her Enemies".Nature.157(3987): 52.Bibcode:1946Natur.157..387R.doi:10.1038/157387a0.S2CID4074331.
  139. ^Bunge, Mario (2020)."Mario Bunge nos dijo:" Se puede ignorar la filosofía, pero no evitarla "".Filosofía&Co.
  140. ^The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics,Preface to the First Edition, trans. Christopher Janaway (Cambridge, 2009), p. 15.
  141. ^abBeiser, Frederick C. (2008).Weltschmerz, Pessimism in German Philosophy, 1860–1900.Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 14–16.ISBN978-0-19-876871-5.Arthur Schopenhauer was the most famous and influential philosopher in Germany from 1860 until the First World War.... Schopenhauer had a profound influence on two intellectual movements of the late 19th century that were utterly opposed to him: neo-Kantianism and positivism. He forced these movements to address issues they would otherwise have completely ignored, and in doing so he changed them markedly.... Schopenhauer set the agenda for his age.
  142. ^Beside Schopenhauer's Corpse
  143. ^Howard, Don (1997).A Peek behind the Veil of Maya: Einstein, Schopenhauer, and the Historical Background of the Conception of Space as a Ground for the Individuation of Physical Systems.University of Pittsburgh Press.Pauli greatly admired Schopenhauer.... Pauli wrote sympathetically about extrasensory perception, noting approvingly that "even such a thoroughly critical philosopher as Schopenhauer not only regarded parapsychological effects going far beyond what is secured by scientific evidence as possible, but even considered them as a support for his philosophy".
  144. ^Bassani, Giuseppe-Franco (15 December 2006). Società Italiana di Fisica (ed.).Ettore Majorana: Scientific Papers.Springer. p. xl.ISBN978-3-540-48091-4.His interest in philosophy, which had always been great, increased and prompted him to reflect deeply on the works of various philosophers, in particular Schopenhauer.
  145. ^Isaacson, Walter (2007).Einstein: His Life and Universe.New York: Simon & Schuster. p. 367.ISBN978-0-7432-6474-7.
  146. ^Howard (1997). p. 87
  147. ^Howard (1997). p. 92
  148. ^Halpern, Paul (2015).Einstein's Dice and Schrödinger's Cat: How Two Great Minds Battled Quantum Randomness to Create a Unified Theory of Physics.Basic Books. p. 189.ISBN978-0-465-04065-0.
  149. ^Howard (1997). p. 132
  150. ^Raymond B. Marcin."Schopenhauers Metaphysics and Contemporary Quantum Theory".David Lindorff referred to Schopenhauer as Pauli's "favorite philosopher", and Pauli himself often expressed his agreement with the main tenet of Schopenhauer's philosophy.... Suzanne Gieser cited a 1952 letter from Pauli to Carl Jung, in which Pauli indicated that, while he accepted Schopenhauer's main tenet that the thing-in-itself of all reality is will.[permanent dead link]
  151. ^See e.g. Magee (2000) 276–278.
  152. ^Nicholas Mathew, Benjamin Walton.The Invention of Beethoven and Rossini: Historiography, Analysis, Criticism.p. 296.
  153. ^Tolstoy's letter to Afanasy Fet on 30 August 1869. "Do you know what this summer has meant for me? Constant raptures over Schopenhauer and a whole series of spiritual delights as I've never experienced before. I have brought all of his works and read him over and over, Kant too by the way. Assuredly no student has ever learned and discovered so much in one semester as I have during this summer. I do not know if I shall ever change my opinion, but at present I am convinced that Schopenhauer is the greatest genius among men. You say he is so-so, he has written a few things on philosophy? What is so-so? It is the whole world in an incomparably beautiful and clear reflection. I have started to translate him. Won't you help me? Indeed, I cannot understand how his name can be unknown. The only explanation for this can only be the one he so often repeats, that is, that there is scarcely anyone but idiots in the world."
  154. ^Thompson, Caleb (2009)."Quietism from the Side of Happiness: Tolstoy, Schopenhauer, War and Peace".Common Knowledge.15(3): 395–411.doi:10.1215/0961754X-2009-020.S2CID145535267.
  155. ^Magee, Bryan (1997).Confessions of a Philosopher.p. 413.
  156. ^Caleb Flamm, Matthew (2002). "Santayana and Schopenhauer".Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society.38(3): 413–431.JSTOR40320900.A thinker of whom it is well known that Santayana had an early, deep admiration, namely, Schopenhauer
  157. ^Yothers, Brian (2015).Sacred Uncertainty: Religious Difference and The Shape of Melville's Career.Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press. p. 13.ISBN978-0-8101-3071-5.
  158. ^Morrison, Simon (2008).Sergey Prokofiev and His World.Princeton University Press. pp. 19, 20.ISBN978-0-691-13895-4.
  159. ^Schopenhauer as Educator
  160. ^Glock, Hans-Johann (2017).A Companion to Wittgenstein.Sussex, UK: Wiley Blackwell. p.60.
  161. ^Glock, Hans-Johann (2000).The Cambridge Companion to Schopenhauer.New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. p.424.
  162. ^Culture & Value, p. 24, 1933–34
  163. ^Malcolm, Norman. Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir. Oxford University Press, 1958, p. 6
  164. ^Russell, Bertrand (1946).History of Western Philosophy.George Allen and Unwin. p. 786.
  165. ^"Writer Nic Pizzolatto on Thomas Ligotti and the Weird Secrets of 'True Detective'".The Wall Street Journal.12 February 2014.
  166. ^M.MoriokaWhat Is Antinatalism? and Other Essays,pp.8–12.
  167. ^Eric Francis Jules Payne (17 February 1895 – 12 January 1983)

Sources[edit]

Further reading[edit]

Biographies[edit]

  • Copleston, Frederick,Arthur Schopenhauer, philosopher of pessimism(Burns, Oates & Washbourne, 1946)
  • Damm, O. F.,Arthur Schopenhauer – eine Biographie(Reclam, 1912)
  • Fischer, Kuno,Arthur Schopenhauer(Heidelberg: Winter, 1893); revised asSchopenhauers Leben, Werke und Lehre(Heidelberg: Winter, 1898).
  • Grisebach, Eduard,Schopenhauer – Geschichte seines Lebens(Berlin: Hofmann, 1876).
  • Hamlyn, D. W.,Schopenhauer,London: Routledge & Kegan Paul (1980, 1985)
  • Hasse, Heinrich,Schopenhauer.(Reinhardt, 1926)
  • Hübscher, Arthur,Arthur Schopenhauer – Ein Lebensbild(Leipzig: Brockhaus, 1938).
  • Mann, Thomas,Schopenhauer(Bermann-Fischer, 1938)
  • Matthews, Jack,Schopenhauer's Will: Das Testament,Nine Point Publishing, 2015.ISBN978-0-9858278-8-5.A recent creative biography by philosophical novelistJack Matthews.
  • Safranski, Rüdiger,Schopenhauer und die wilden Jahre der Philosophie – Eine Biographie,hard cover Carl Hanser Verlag, München 1987,ISBN978-3-446-14490-3,pocket edition Fischer:ISBN978-3-596-14299-6.
  • Safranski, Rüdiger,Schopenhauer and the Wild Years of Philosophy,trans. Ewald Osers (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1989)
  • Schneider, Walther,Schopenhauer – Eine Biographie(Vienna: Bermann-Fischer, 1937).
  • Wallace, William,Life of Arthur Schopenhauer(London: Scott, 1890; repr., St. Clair Shores, Mich.: Scholarly Press, 1970)
  • Zimmern, Helen,Arthur Schopenhauer: His Life and His Philosophy(London: Longmans, Green & Co, 1876)

Other books[edit]

  • App, Urs.Arthur Schopenhauer and China.Sino-Platonic PapersNr. 200 (April 2010)(PDF, 8.7 Mb PDF, 164 p.). Contains extensive appendixes with transcriptions and English translations of Schopenhauer's early notes about Buddhism and Indian philosophy.
  • App, Urs,Schopenhauers Kompass. Die Geburt einer Philosophie.UniversityMedia, Rorschach/ Kyoto 2011.ISBN978-3-906000-02-2
  • Atwell, John.Schopenhauer on the Character of the World, The Metaphysics of Will.
  • Atwell, John,Schopenhauer, The Human Character.
  • Edwards, Anthony.An Evolutionary Epistemological Critique of Schopenhauer's Metaphysics.123 Books, 2011.
  • Copleston, Frederick,Schopenhauer: Philosopher of Pessimism,1946 (reprinted London: Search Press, 1975).
  • Gardiner, Patrick,1963.Schopenhauer.Penguin Books.
  • Janaway, Christopher, 2002.Schopenhauer: A Very Short introduction.Oxford University Press.ISBN978-0192802590
  • Janaway, Christopher, 2003.Self and World in Schopenhauer's Philosophy.Oxford University Press.ISBN978-0-19-825003-6
  • Magee, Bryan,The Philosophy of Schopenhauer,Oxford University Press (1988, reprint 1997).ISBN978-0-19-823722-8
  • Marcin, Raymond B.In Search of Schopenhauer's Cat: Arthur Schopenhauer's Quantum-Mystical Theory of Justice.Washington, D.C.: The Catholic University of America Press, 2005.ISBN978-0813214306
  • Neymeyr, Barbara, 1996 (reprint 2011): Ästhetische Autonomie als Abnormität. Kritische Analysen zu Schopenhauers Ästhetik im Horizont seiner Willensmetaphysik. (= Quellen und Studien zur Philosophie. Band 42). Walter de Gruyter, Berlin / New York 1996,ISBN3-11-015229-0.(reprint 2011, De Gruyter Berlin / Boston).
  • Mannion, Gerard, "Schopenhauer, Religion and Morality – The Humble Path to Ethics", Ashgate Press, New Critical Thinking in Philosophy Series, 2003, 314pp.
  • Trottier, Danick.L'influence de la philosophie schopenhauerienne dans la vie et l'oeuvre de Richard Wagner; et, Qu'est-ce qui séduit, ob sắc de, magnétise le philosophe dans l'art des sons? deux études en esthétique musicale,Université du Québec à Montréal, Département de musique, 2000.
  • Zimmern, Helen,Arthur Schopenhauer, his Life and Philosophy,London,Longman, and Co.,1876.
  • Kastrup, Bernardo.Decoding Schopenhauer's Metaphysics – The key to understanding how it solves the hard problem of consciousness and the paradoxes of quantum mechanics.Winchester/Washington, iff Books, 2020.
  • de Botton, Alain:The Consolations of Philosophy.Hamish Hamilton, London 2000.ISBN0-14-027661-0(Chapter:Consolation for a Broken Heart).

Fiction[edit]

Articles[edit]

External links[edit]